Ludwig Feuerbach: Lectures on the Essence of Religion. Ralph Manheim translation. New York: Harper and Row, 1967 [1846].
Ludwig Feuerbach: Principles of the Philosophy of the Future. Manfred Vogel translation. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1986 [1843].
Although he attended many lectures offered by G. W. F. Hegel at the University of Berlin, Feuerbach broke with his professor on the question of materialism, rejecting Hegel’s dialectical immanentism. He also firmly denied both the Creator-God of the Bible and any suggestion of philosophic dualism. He was a thoroughgoing materialist, although not a ‘dialectical materialist,’ like his younger contemporary, Karl Marx.
Students at the University of Heidelberg, where Feuerbach had attended classes before transferring to Berlin, invited him to deliver a series of thirty lectures on “the Essence of Religion,” which he published in 1846. Speaking shortly before the revolutionary year of 1848, Feuerbach began by observing that “today every man, even if he supposes himself to be supremely nonpartisan, is at least theoretically a partisan, though he may not know it or want to be,” since “today political interest engulfs all other interests and political events keep us in a state of constant turmoil.” Indeed, “today it is actually the duty—especially of us nonpolitical Germans—to forget everything for the sake of politics”; more, “mankind” itself “must at certain times forget all other tasks and activities for the sake of one particular task and activity if it wishes to achieve something complete and worthwhile.” Inasmuch as religion “is to be sure closely connected with politics,” and we now “demand that the word become flesh, the spirit matter,” having become “as sick of political as we are of philosophical idealism,” we are “determined to become political materialists.” Feuerbach’s critique of religion serves as the foundation of a republican politics, a ‘youth movement.’ At around the same time, Tocqueville would publish his book on the French Revolution, remarking that it was the political inexperience of the French revolutionaries that led to the Terror. Feuerbach does not consider that possibility, and neither would most Germans, for the next hundred years.
“Truly free, uncompromising, unconventional thinking, thinking that aspires to be fruitful, not to say decisive, requires an unconventional, free, and uncompromising life,” he tells his young listeners. “And anyone who wishes in his thinking to get to the bottom of human affairs must have his two feet physically, bodily on their foundation,” namely nature, “cast[ing] aside all extravagant, supernatural, and unnatural ideas and fantasies.” Readily seeing through the calculated ambiguities of Bacon and Hobbes (he had written a study of Bacon’s philosophy, published in the 1830s), he sees, adopts, and advocates their materialism, while reserving especial praise for Spinoza, “the only modern philosopher to have provided the first elements of a critique and explanation of religion and theology; the first to have offered a positive opposition to theology; the first to have stated, in terms that have become classical, that the world cannot be regarded as the work or product of a personal being acting in accordance with aims and purposes; the first to have brought out the all-importance of nature for the philosophy of religion.” In response to Spinoza, Leibniz is “the first modern German philosopher” to earn “the honor, or dishonor, of having once again tied philosophy to the apron strings of theology,” an effort Feuerbach ridicules as the philosophical equivalent of the astronomical contortions of Tycho Brahe, who vainly attempted to combine elements of the Copernican system with the system of Ptolemy that it had correctly replaced. To mix philosophy and theology, as Leibniz attempts, can result only in “a monstrosity” because theology holds only the sacred as true, “whereas to philosophy, only what it holds true is sacred.” “All my works have been written in opposition to a period when every effort was made to force mankind back into the darkness of bygone centuries,” the centuries before the modern Enlightenment. Even the pious philosophers of earlier centuries understood the need to separate philosophy and religion, “arguing that religion is grounded on divine wisdom and authority, while philosophy is grounded solely on human wisdom.” But “the most recent philosophers”—Leibniz but, more impressively, Hegel—stand for “the identity of philosophy and religion, at least as far as content and substance are concerned.” “I criticized the Hegelian philosophy,” with its dialectical immanentism, its ‘Absolute Spirit,’ “for regarding the essential as nonessential and the nonessential as essential in religion.” Against this, I, Feuerbach, declared the essence of religion to be “precisely what philosophy regards as mere form,” immaterial in both senses of the word. “I replaced the abstract, merely cogitated cosmic being known as God by the reality of the world, or nature,” while also replacing “the rational being deprived of his senses, which philosophy has extracted out of man, by the real, sensuous man endowed with reason.” There is, for example, no immortality of the individual human ‘soul.’ “Intellectual, ethical, or moral immortality is solely the immortality a man gains through his works,” and his soul, animating those works, is only “what he passionately loves, what he does with passion,” and “men’s souls are as diverse, as particular as men themselves.” Feuerbach thus full-throatedly endorses not only the materialism of the moderns but the individualism of the moderns and the ‘democracy’ of the moderns, their esteem for liberty defined as doing what one likes, passionately.
Accordingly, rightly understood, “theology is anthropology” because it “expresses nothing other than the deified essence of man”; that is what ‘revealed religion’ reveals. Overlying nature, convention skews man’s conception of himself and therefore his conception of the divine; “the pagan is a patriot,” his gods the gods of his polis, while “the Christian is a cosmopolitan” whose God is universal. Universalism thrives on the habit of generalization, abstraction, and sure enough, “Christianity is idealism, an edifice crowned by a natureless God or spirit who makes the world by merely thinking and willing, and apart from whose thinking and willing the world has no existence.” But, Feuerbach asserts, there is only nature—no ideals and no God or gods. The only difference between human nature and the rest of nature is human consciousness; he intends to awaken that consciousness to the emptiness of religious belief (in these lectures) and of philosophic idealism (in Principles of the Philosophy of the Future), to “demonstrate that the powers which man worships and fears in his religious life, which he seeks to propitiate even with bloody human sacrifices, are merely creatures of his own unfree, fearful mind and of his ignorant unformed intelligence.” Morally and politically, this means that he wants “man, who is always unconsciously governed and determined by his own essence alone, may in future consciously take his own human essence as the law and determining ground, the aim and measure, of his ethical and political life.” No fear of God is the beginning of wisdom. This will begin the project “to transform theologians into anthropologists, lovers of God into lovers of man, candidates for the next world into students of this world, religious and political flunkeys of heavenly and earthly monarchs and lords into free, self-reliant citizens of the earth.”
“Hear, O Israel.” Religious men hearken to nature’s terrifying thunder, a noise perceived through “the ear, the organ of terror”—the ear, which is “the womb of the gods.” Feuerbach goes so far as to claim that “if man had only eyes, hands and the senses of taste and smell, he would have no religion, for all these senses are organs of critique and skepticism.” The fear and love commended by religions are passions of dependency, not self-reliance. The ultimate sign of human helplessness is mortality: “If man did not die, if he lived forever, if there were no such thing as death, there would be no religion.” Belief in immortality is man’s defense against death (presumably including Feuerbach’s work, which he could only justify by saying that it is an effort to achieve the only possible form of immortality). Primitive man worships nature, which he deifies; Feuerbach calls this religion but not theism, a term he reserves for belief in a god or gods distinct from nature and man. “It is theism, theology, that has wrenched man out of his relationship with the world, isolated him, made him into an arrogant self-centered being who exalts himself above nature.” “In religion man projects his essence,” but primitive man (with unintended modesty) merely projected his sensations, having yet to develop the abstract thought that enables him to conceive of an abstract or spiritual god. Primitive man is entirely dependent upon nature; religion registers human dependency; primitive religion deifies nature because primitive man fears nature, divinizes it, hoping to propitiate the imagined divinities that are nothing more than aspects of nature. We should not make this mistake, return to paganism, “since man’s true culture and true task is to take things as they are, to make no more, but also no less of them than they are. Nature religion, pantheism, makes too much of nature”—the earth is indeed our mother, but we are now adults— while “conversely, idealism, theism Christian make too little of it, and indeed ignore it.” Politically, this means that while we should understand but not follow the pagans in making “the nature in which they lived and breathed, to which alone they owed their individual character, in short, the nature of their country, [into] an object of religious worship,” modern man might still respect “the nature of this country,” his country, “for it is to this country alone that I owe my life and what I am.” “How untrue we Germans have become to our source, our mother, and how unlike her, thanks to Christianity which taught us that heaven is our home.”
Feuerbach further claims that egoism is the essence of religion, “the self-assertion of man in accordance with his nature and consequently of his reason.” Since “to man life is the supreme good,” man inclines to idolize, to deify, anything that protects or enhances his life. But these idols are in fact “dependent on man; they are gods only insofar as they serve his being, as they are useful, helpful, appropriate to it.” Christianity only replaced paganism when the idols were seen as useless, “because the pagan gods did not give them what they wanted,” whereas the Christian God is the “very essence and likeness” of man himself, who by now had begun to think abstractly, therefore seeking a universal, all-knowing, all-powerful deity. This enables ‘we moderns,’ we post-Christians, to discover the “ultimate subjective ground of religion in human egoism,” human desire. Aristotle’s god, the ‘god of the philosophers,’ gains no adherents among most people because it is neither a helpful nor a harmful god. It is useless. “In calling egoism the ground and essence of religion, I am not finding fault with religion,” which only reflects the nature, the essence of man in this regard. Rather, Feuerbach faults an ‘idealistic’ religion that holds man above nature, “tak[ing] an unboundedly egoistic, contemptuous attitude toward nature,” exhibiting an egoism no longer bounded by the limits of nature alone, as seen “in the Christian belief in miracles and immortality,” evidence of “an unnatural, supernatural, and chimerical egoism, exceeding the limits of necessary, natural egoism.”
But if religion expresses natural human egoism, why do so many religions commend self-abnegation? Because a man might be a fanatic, carrying his natural feelings too far. Or he might hope “to gain the favor of his gods, who grant him everything he desires”—a cunning, self-serving self-abnegation, “only a form, a means of self-affirmation, of self-love.” This is the psychology of religious sacrifice, whether the sacrifice of animals, or “bloody human sacrifice” seen among pagans, or Christian sacrifice, which partakes “of a different, namely, psychological, spiritual order,” a sacrifizio dell’intelleto. In the spirit of Machiavelli, Feuerbach alleges that “the Church has at all times advocated moral, spiritual, and mental self-emasculation.” Christians are communists, “but communists out of egoism”; their “generous, imposing sacrifices” do not differ in principle” from “foul and niggardly sacrifices.” It is true that any attempt to combat “human egoism in the highly developed sense” amounts to “sheer absurdity and madness,” since “the design underlying all human impulses, strivings, and actions, is to satisfy the needs of human nature, human egoism.” But only with full ‘consciousness’ of the grounding of self-interest in nature, with no supernatural confusion added.
It is noteworthy that in the first nine of this series of thirty lectures, Feuerbach makes no arguments. He asserts. It may be that his failure to philosophize serves a rhetorical strategy, saying atheistic things that will shock many among his young audience while encouraging those who already deny the existence of God. He begins his tenth lecture in much the same style. It is egoism, he claims, that makes dependency possible (“where there is no egoism, there is no feeling of dependency”) and it is egoism that revolts against dependency (“I love freedom of movement”). Human beings are dependent, but not upon God. “How untrue we Germans have become to our source, our mother, and how unlike her, thanks to Christianity which taught us that heaven is our home.” Be true to yourselves, young Germans; turn away from religion to nature and to Fatherland.
But now he begins to philosophize, taking aim at the “cosmological proof” of God’s existence, that there must be some ultimate Cause-of-causes, some First Mover of all subsequent movements in nature. Feuerbach dismisses this as proof only of human psychological neediness, not of the existence of God. “This need of mine to break off the endless series is no proof of a real break in the series of a real beginning and end.” “God” is only a name for our own inability to discern the true origin of things, or indeed if there was an origin at all, since the cosmos might be eternal. And “what is to prevent me from going beyond God?”—continuing the inquiry into what came before “In the beginning….” As far as we can see, “Nature has no beginning and no end”; politically (as it were) this means that “nature does not culminate in a monarchic summit; it is a republic.” Continuing to follow the evidence presented by his senses, Feuerbach says, “I cannot derive my body from my mind—for I have to eat or to be able to eat before I can think.” Reason presupposes my senses; my senses do not presuppose reason. “No more, or perhaps even less, can I derive nature from God.” That “the world of the senses is real” is an ineluctable truth in psychology, anthropology, and philosophy. Only the religions deny this, and neither do they, initially, since “Man’s first belief is his belief in the truth of the senses,” the foundation of “nature religion.” “The first beings of whom man had immediate certainty and consequently his first gods were sensuous objects”; more, “men’s senses were themselves his first gods.” He has no philosophic need for any others, inasmuch as “what a man does not know by his own lights, he does not know at all.”
What is nature? It is “the sum of all the sensuous forces, things, and beings which man distinguishes from himself as other than human.” Nature is no god but “a manifold, public, actual being which can be perceived with all the senses.” The physical attributes of the Biblical God—power, eternity, infinity—are all “rooted in nature.” His moral attributes are rooted in human nature, attributes that make Him useful to man. God’s moral and also his intellectual traits are nothing more than projections of natural human capacities upon an imaginary perfect being, proving that man is indeed egoistic. The infinity attributed to God only proves that man is “infinitely fond of himself,” ready to worship his own image. “In theology,” as distinguished from psychology, anthropology, and philosophy, “things are not thought and willed because they exist, they exist because they are thought and willed.” It is a teaching that inverts “the order of nature,” an inversion that is in a sense natural to man, even if mistaken, because man is rational, a being that “sets the class or class concept before the species and individuals, the abstract before the concrete”; “this explains and resolves all the difficulties and contradictions arising from attempts to explain the world as God’s creation,” a something inexplicably created out of nothing. “God is nothing other than the sum of generic concepts,” concepts generated by the human mind’s natural inclination to think of such abstractions as time and space, then to assume that these exist prior to the real things, the material, sensually perceived things. That is, abstractions are concepts, constructed in the human mind, which constructs or ‘creates’ by its nature—still another godlike attribute of human nature that human beings naturally attribute to their gods. Language itself abstracts, unable to express the particular, and so takes over our minds, making our minds think abstractly. Those among us who don’t think too much, those “who are more concerned with life than with study, who spend more of their time out of doors than in libraries, whose occupations and temperaments lead them to observe real beings,” understand this better than bookish pedants and priests.
Feuerbach is careful not to dismiss abstractions entirely. “I do not deny the existence of wisdom, goodness, beauty; I deny only that these class concepts are independent beings, either as gods, or as attributes of God, or as Platonic Ideas, or as self-positing Hegelian concepts; I merely maintain that they exist only in wise, good, beautiful individuals” as their attributes, as “characteristics or determinations of individuality,” not as “beings in themselves.” In terms of physical nature, my form consists of the outer limits of my body; someone can trace the outline of my body if I lie down on a large piece of cardboard, but that outline abstracts from my body itself, having no reality beyond the ink or carbon left behind by the instrument that traced it.
Feuerbach next turns to a refutation of the teleological proof of God’s existence, often called the argument from design—the Apostle Paul’s testimony, that the perceivable order of the world implies an ‘orderer,’ God. Feuerbach rejoins that “what man interprets as the purposiveness of nature is in reality nothing other than the unity of the world, the harmony of its causes and effects, and in general the all-embracing order of things in nature,” one that “gives man the impression of wisdom and purposiveness in nature,” but does not prove it. Feuerbach equally denies that the world “owe[s] its existence to any accident,” the “patently irrational notion” that it derived from “the fortuitous clash of atoms,” a fantasy “tantamount to explaining the genesis of a literary work, the Annales of Ennius, for example, by a chance combination of letters.” The sum of things does not exist due to intention or to chance, as far as perceiving and reasoning man can know. Being is ‘because’ it is, not ‘in order for’ anything or by fortunate concatenation. We only know that the universe is, not how or why, and we know that it is thanks to our senses, our only means of knowing anything.
And even if teleology were real, this wouldn’t prove the existence of God or gods. “God is merely the hypostasized and objectified essence of the human imagination.” We “can give no reason for a natural law,” even if “analogy leads us to the belief, or rather the certainty, that the law has a natural cause.” To infer the existence of God from the natural order is to confuse nature, which is a ‘republic’ in which all elements interplay, with a monarchic Being who acts miraculously, counter to nature, by fiat. There “is only one regime” in nature, a republic. In human nature, “my head may be the president of my life, but it is not an absolute monarch, king by divine right,” having the same substance “of flesh and blood” as the stomach, the heart, or any of the other organs. It rules but “does not differ from them in kind, in race,” exerting no “despotic power.” if it “tries to play the prince and make unnatural demands” on the other organs it will be “stripped of its command.” And “just as a republic, at least the democratic republic I have in mind, is governed not by princes but by representatives of the people, so nature is not governed by gods, but only by natural forces, natural laws, and natural elements or beings.” To posit the existence of God, an immaterial being, “breaks off this necessary connection” between physical things, between the physical senses and the physical objects they perceive. “Calvin says explicitly that God in the Old Testament created light before the sun, in order that men might see that the beneficent effects of light were not necessarily connected with the sun, that even without the sun God is capable of doing what He now, in the customary but by no means necessary course of nature, does by means of the sun.” But “if there is a God, why the world, why nature,” a being that cannot achieve the perfection of God? “It has often been said that the world is inexplicable without a God; but the exact opposite is true: if there is a God, the existence of a world becomes inexplicable; for then the world is utterly superfluous,” as “nothing follows from God; everything beside Him is superfluous, futile, meaningless.” Biblical religion is nihilism, its claim of something coming out of nothing utterly irrational not only in terms of efficient and material causation but in terms of teleological causation, since there is no rational purpose for a perfect Being to create an imperfect thing. Moslem theologians are more rigorously rational than their Christian counterparts, maintaining “quite correctly from the standpoint of theology” that all things are entirely dependent upon God’s will, that there is no nature that acts in any way independently of God. Fire could cool things, if God willed that. ‘Christian rationalism’ of the sort propounded by Aquinas is only “theism attenuated by atheism or naturalism or cosmism, in short, by elements opposed to theism”—a “limited, restricted, and incomplete atheism or naturalism.” A God “who acts only in accordance with natural laws” is “a God only in name.” “Only an unlimited, wonder-working God, bound by no laws, a God who, at least in man’s faith and imagination, can save us from all trouble and affliction, is truly a God,” but a God “who is no more powerful than doctors and medicines, is an utterly superfluous, unnecessary God,” an “absurdity.” The choice is stark: no monarchy or absolute monarchy, no God and “an absolute God like the God of our fathers.” Make up your minds, young Germans.
To think straight, “man starts from what is closest to him, from the present, and draws from it inferences concerning what is further away; this procedure is common to atheist and theist alike.” The difference is that theists are, paradoxically, anthropocentric, attributing human qualities to an imagined God and (especially in paganism) to a mythicized, ‘personalized’ cosmos, while atheists “takes nature as his starting point and goes on to the study of man” as one instance of the nature of which he is a part. “The atheist puts nature before art. The theist puts art before nature; in his view, nature is a product of God’s art, or, what amounts to the same thing, of divine art.” The theist mistakenly derives “the unconscious from consciousness, rather than consciousness from the unconscious.” But the mind is no disembodied spirit breathed into man by a disembodied God; the mind is an effect of brain activity. The German mystic Jacob Böhme tried to get around this by claiming that God is corporeal, working himself up into spirituality. This “supernatural naturalism” deifies matter and is merely a product of Bōhme’s fertile, or perhaps febrile, imagination. The claim lacks any evidence, not even Scriptural evidence. “Either God or nature! There is no third, middle term combining the two.” Luckily, “for all his extravagant faith, man is unable to repress or relinquish his natural human reason,” which enables him to pursue “independent activity, diligence, education, self-mastery, and effort”—all needed, since “nature throws man upon his own resources; it does not help him unless he helps himself; it lets him sink if he cannot swim,” as part of nature, which changes perpetually, discarding one aspect of itself in favor of another, then discarding that one. Feuerbach slashes at God with Ockham’s razor: “If there is an eye watching over me, why do I need an eye of my own, why should I look out for myself?” On the grounds of religious passivity, even a man who shaves his own beard rebels against the course of nature, God’s creation.
As for that creation, Feuerbach dismisses creatio ex nihilo as “a mere evasion”: “Where did the spirit get the nonspiritual, material corporeal substances of which the world consists?” And if, with Hegel, one claims that “He created it out of Himself, out of spiritual matter,” “how does real matter issue from spiritual matter, from God?” “What makes the world world, what makes body body and matter matter, is something that cannot be theologically or philosophically deduced from anything else; it cannot be derived, but simply is, and can be understood only in terms of itself.” Religion is the realm of imagination, of poetry, of man making gods for himself to worship. “I should merely like man to stop setting his hear on things which are no longer in keeping with his nature and needs, and which he therefore can believe and worship only by coming into conflict with himself” as a rational being. Being a thing of the imagination, a thing of poetry, of making, religion permits a morality of man’s own making. “Russian prostitutes are…full of reverence for the saints. When they receive visitors, the first thing they do is to cover their icons and put out the candles.” No less ridiculously, in Feuerbach’s estimation, a Christian “need only hang the cloak of Christian love, of divine grace, over God’s punitive justice and proceed to do anything he pleases.” More comprehensively, man’s imagination, “molded by his nature,” makes God “in his image” and remakes nature, too, “into an image of man.” The imagination enables men to behave as despots over all. Only reason can discern the natural limits of man, who in reality lives within a cosmos that is “blind and deaf to the desires and complaints of man.” Not only does man not need religion for obtaining happiness, religion impedes his pursuit of it. But “as soon as man opens his eyes, as soon as he ceases to be beclouded by religious ideas and sees reality for what it is, his heart revolts against the notion of Providence…by the way in which it saves one man and lets another go to his doom, destines one man to happiness and prosperity and others to abject misery.” Only Enlightened materialism truly promises justice.
While “religion arises solely in the night of ignorance,” a night in which dreams, products of the imagination, rule human minds, it “also springs from man’s need of light, of culture, or at least of the products of culture,” being “the first, still crude and vulgar form of human culture.” This “why every epoch, every important stage in the history of human civilization, begins with religion.” It must not end there, however, since “religion merely suppresses the symptoms of evil, not its causes.” The “radical cure” of “bestiality and barbarism” comes “only where the actions of mankind flow from causes inherent in the nature of man,” in “harmony between principle and practice, cause and effect; only then can man be complete and whole.” The union of principle or theory and practice may be seen in modern science, which may be undertaken by the right kind of education. “All history down to our own times demonstrates that the greatest horrors are compatible with religion, but not with education,” an asseveration that begs the reply, ‘Just you wait!’ Be this as it may, Feuerbach points to the supposed impossibility of “progress” within the horizons of traditional religions. “A new era also requires a new view of the first elements and foundations of human existence; it requires—if we wish to retain the word—a new religion!” To establish this new religion, the old ones must be extirpated; mere religious toleration is not enough. In this new religion, work will replace prayer. Whereas “a Christian’s wishes exceed the limits of nature and of the world,” atheism “is a complete and thoroughgoing rationalism,” one that refuses the illusory promise of immortality the old religions offer, the appeal to wishful thinking, replacing it with the reality of the true God, the “unity and equality of the human race,” of which the false God of the religions is only the “personified” disembodiment. “Those human desires that are not imaginary and fantastic are fulfilled in the course of history, of the future,” desires that “will someday be fulfilled,” will “one day be reality.” “We must therefore modify our goals and exchange divinity, in which only man’s groundless and gratuitous desires are fulfilled, for the human race or human nature, religion for education, the hereafter in heaven for the hereafter on earth, that is, the historical future, the future of mankind.” And just as the old religions insist on a public presence, so should the new ‘religion of humanity.’ “The atheism that fears the light is an unworthy and hollow atheism,” the atheism or privately held, esoteric zeteticism of the old philosophers. “True atheism, the atheism that does not shun the light,” does not merely deny the existence of God but affirms “man’s true being.” True atheism is “liberal, openhanded, openminded,” joyful, life-affirming. “We must replace the love of God by the love of man as the only true religion,” its task being “to transform friends of God into friends of man, believers into thinkers, devotees of prayer into devotees of work, candidates for the hereafter into students of this world, Christians, who, by their own profession and admission, are half animal, half angel, into men, into whole men.”
And who shall be the evangelists of the religion of humanity? “I am not for eliminating the cultural aristocracy. Far from it.” You, my university students, can become the vanguard of human progress. The new aristocrats will be aristocrats of the intellect, but deploying intellect in a way that departs in some measure even from previous ‘moderns.’
To do so, they will need not only to reject religion as it has been, not only to plan the religion of the future, but to become the philosophers of the future. His Principles of the Philosophy of the Future provides the roadmap to this new way of life. The “task” of the philosophy of the future is to lead philosophy “from the realm of ‘departed souls’ back into the realm of embodied and living souls; of pulling philosophy down from the divine, self-sufficient bliss in the realm of ideas into human misery,” the “mud in which [man on earth] has been embedded.” That is, Platonic and even Hegelian philosophy (“the philosophy of the absolute”) levitate above human misery instead of helping to remedy it. In this, Feuerbach is not far from Marx’s preference for changing the world instead of attempting to understand it, and he regards the first task of the philosophy of the present, prelude to the philosophy of the future, to provide a “critique of human philosophy through the critique of divine philosophy”—a foreshadowing of the ‘critical thinking’ of Marx and his successors to this day.
The book consists of 65 numbered sections. The central, thirty-third section bears the number traditionally symbolizing Jesus Christ, Who is said to have died at age thirty-three. And the first step toward the philosophy of the future, according to Feuerbach, was taken by Christians, the Protestants who provided a “religious anthropology,” discoursing not so much on God ‘in himself’ but “what he is for man.” Philosophers took the next step, denying that God ‘in himself’ exists, instead claiming that God is “the essence of reason itself.” “That which is object in theism” became in philosophic hands the “subject in speculative philosophy,” with God now the “thinking ego” of man.” Feuerbach charges that “ordinary theology” presents a “self-contradictory” God, one who is human in all his thoughts and feelings yet “supposed to be a non-human and superhuman being,” an “abstracted being”—that is, a being human beings have abstracted from their own distinctive characteristics. The men Feuerbach calls “speculative” philosophers—Descartes and Leibniz, eventually followed by Hegel—rejected God as ” a being of fantasy, a far-removed, indefinite, and cloudy being,” making Him (really It) “a present and definite being,” not a holy but an absolute spirit. “Absolute idealism is nothing but the realized divine mind of Leibnizian theism; it is pure mind systematically elaborated,” as for example in Hegel’s Logic, wherein “the objects of thought are not distinguished from the essence of thought” because the Absolute Spirit is immanent in all of being; Hegelianism is a new form of pantheism, first proposed in modern philosophy by Spinoza. Feuerbach contends that pantheism is in fact “the naked truth of theism” because the things God created, according to the Bible, must have existed in God’s mind before he created them, so the mind of God does indeed comprise all things. That is, if God made matter, “how, why, and from what” did he make it” “To this, theism gives no answer” apart from mere fictions. Only pantheism gives a rationally consistent answer, if one remains within a theological framework.
It only remains for Feuerbach to reject that framework. In Hegelianism, modern science studies the material manifestations of the Absolute Spirit. “But if we were once to have no more objects and no world apart from God, so would we also have no more God—not only an ideal and imagine, but a real being—apart from this world”—a point, it should be said, that Spinoza and the rabbis who attacked him understood very well. “Pantheism connects…atheism with theism, the negation of God with God; God is a material or, in the language of Spinoza, an extended being.” “Matter is not God; it is, rather, the finite, the nondivine, the negation of God,” and pantheism amounts to “theological atheism or theological materialism.” Pantheism is “nothing other than the essence of the modern era elevated to a divine being and to a religiophilosophic principle.”
Feuerbach dissents from pantheism on ‘Ockhamite’ grounds: If you say God is immanent in matter, why study God at all? You only need to study matter. Medieval scholars were poor scientists because they “had no interest in nature.” ‘We moderns’ no longer know much about God, devils, and angels because “mankind in the modern era lost the organism for the supernatural world and its secrets,” having lost “the disposition toward the supernatural world.” That is, knowledge follows not the head, not reason, but the heart. They were led to his heart-change by Spinoza, “the Moses of modern freethinkers and materialists”—a thought suggesting that Feuerbach conceives of himself as the Christ of such men. Spinoza has done the preliminary work of negating theoretical theology; Baconian empiricism negates practical theology by marking out experience, including experimental science, as a realm of ‘not-God.’ But empiricism by itself is sub-philosophical; modern philosophy must elevate it to theoretical status, and that is where Feuerbach comes in.
“Matter is an essential object of reason,” inasmuch as “if there were not matter, reason would have no stimulus and substance for thinking and thus no content.” In a sense, “God exists,” for moderns, but only as “a tabula rasa, an empty being, a mere idea,” a manifestation of “our ego, our mind, and our essence.” “Modern philosophy proceeded from theology; it is indeed nothing other than theology dissolved and transformed into philosophy,” from Descartes to Hegel. “The culmination of modern philosophy is the Hegelian philosophy,” a “pantheistic idealism.” This idealism must be purged from philosophy altogether by the philosophers of the future, following the lead of Feuerbach. “The historical necessity and justification of modern philosophy attaches itself…mainly to the critique of Hegel.”
The problem with Hegel: his Absolute Spirit, unfolding dialectically in time, amounts to God’s “self-liberation from matter,” albeit strictly within the human mind. Some of the previous philosophers had taught that philosophers, and philosophers alone, liberate themselves from matter, that this “self-liberation [is] the virtue of a human being,” but they didn’t posit anything like the Absolute Spirit, and so did not embrace historicism, the notion that all events up to Hegel’s metaphysics were ‘relative to’ and propaedeutic of the ‘end of History,’ the culmination of this eons-long process. In Hegel’s theory, “God is God only because he overcomes and negates matter,” which is the negation of God. “Only the negation of [this] negation is the true affirmation,” but as far as Feuerbach is concerned this returns us to “the point from which we started—in the bosom of God.” “The secret of the Hegelian dialectic lies, in the last analysis, only in the fact that it negates theology by philosophy and then, in turn, negates philosophy by theology,” resulting in “a self-contradictory, atheistic God.” This isn’t quite fair to Hegel, for whom God or the Absolute Spirit is not a ‘he’ but an ‘it’; it would be better to complain that this returns us to a sort of neo-Platonism, a triumph of mental force over brute matter—the victory of a form of energy over matter. [2] At any rate, Feuerbach alleges that the “speculative identity of mind and matter” seen in Hegel is “nothing more than the unfortunate contradiction of the modern era,” which cannot quite relinquish the divine. “Just as the divine essence is nothing other than the essence of man liberated from the limits of nature, so is the essence of absolute idealism nothing other than the essence of subjective idealism liberated from its limits, and, indeed, rational limits, of subjectivity, that is, from sensation or objectivity in general.” ‘Absolute’ theology, seen not only in Hegel but in such non- or pre-historicist idealists as Kant and Fichte, mistakenly attempts to ‘objectify’ the goings-on in the brain, thereby alienating man “from his own essence and activity.”
Such philosophers quite literally talk “nonsense”—non-sense—by rejecting the evidence of the senses or rather attempting to overcome sense-impressions with ideational illusions of various sorts. “The proof that something is has no other meaning that something is not only thought of.” Anything that is only thought of doesn’t really exist. Concretely, if “I have one hundred dollars only in the mind, but the other dollars in the hand,” the dollars in my mind “exist just for me” but the dollars in my hand “also exist for others” because “they can be felt and seen.” Feuerbach derives the thought of right from what would seem the unpromising soil of materialism by arguing that if I am merely an idea in the head of someone else, “I must put up with everything.” Other persons could “portray me in a way that would be a true caricature without my being able to protest against it,” whereas “when I am still really existing, then I can thwart him, then I can make him feel and prove to him that there is a vast difference between me as I am in his conception and me as I am in reality, namely, between me as his object and me as a subject.” As an abstraction, I am only “a being made up and invented, without the essence of being,” but as a material, sensually perceived object, “I am a liberal,” a man free of anyone else’s imagining and conceptualizing. To think ‘abstractly’ is to lose all sense of reality, of limits. Materialism is of the earth, earthy, and that is a very good thing because without limits “we would arrive at the negation of all rights, for rights are founded only on the reality of the difference between this and that,” difference sensually perceived. A real philosopher, a follower of the “new philosophy” of Feuerbach, sets material, sensually perceived limits on his thinking. “The reality of the idea is…sensation. But reality is the truth of the idea; thus, sensation is the truth of the idea”; “truth, reality, and sensation are identical.”
In the thirty-third, central section of the book, Feuerbach rejects the spiritualized love of Platonism, philosophic eros (what Marx would soon deride as “a passion of the head”) and the spiritual love of Christianity, caritas or agape. “Love is passion,” material passion, “and only passion is the hallmark of existence.” The lover distinguishes, sensually, this from that, who or what he loves from those persons or things he does not love. That is, the core of Feuerbach’s teaching makes the senses do the work of what rationalist philosophers and religious men had bestowed upon reasoning, with its eros for the truth, and/or divine inspiration, with its transformational and creative spiritual love, the love of a holy God, a God separate from His creation. It is “in feelings,” not in thoughts, that “the deepest and highest truths are concealed,” since “love is the true ontological proof of the existence of an object apart from our mind. “That object whose being affords you pleasure and whose nonbeing affords you pain—that alone exists.” “The new philosophy itself is basically nothing other than the essence of feeling elevated to consciousness; it only affirms in reason and with reason what every man—the real man—professes in his heart,” which “does not want abstract, metaphysical, or theological objects” but “real and sensuous objects and beings.” This is indeed a philosophy well designed to attract young men stuck in a university classroom.
“The secret of immediate knowledge is sensation.” This is Feuerbach’s version of Locke’s “self-evident truths,” rejected by the previous German Romantics and by subsequent German philosophers (Nietzsche, Heidegger) as English, all-too-English. But Feuerbach regards the English philosopher is the true philosopher of liberty.
Feuerbach nonetheless does not reject ideas as illusory, if they are rightly understood. If so understood, ideas are “refined” sense perceptions, as distinguished from “the vulgar and crude senses or through the eyes of the anatomists or chemists.” Such refinement comes about when we see that we cannot by ourselves distinguish between genuine sense impressions and illusions. “Only through communication and conversation between man and man do ideas arise. Not alone, but only with others, does one reach notions and reason in general” because “that which I alone perceive I doubt,” whereas “only that which the other also perceives is certain.” This doesn’t mean that truth is socially constructed, as some later thinkers will claim, but rather than it is socially confirmed. Genuine, “objective” ideas are those that are “acknowledged by another person apart from you for whom they are an object.” It is not clear why illusions might not also be shared, as they surely can be, and indeed as they must have been, up to this point, according to Feuerbach himself. At best, the requirement of ‘intersubjectivity’ might disqualify such ideas as cannot be shared; it cannot verify such ideas that can be shared and more, believed.
“Only now, in the modern era, has mankind arrived again—as once in Greece after the demise of the Oriental dream world—at the sensuous, that is, the unfalsified and objective perception of the sensuous, that is, of the real.” Contra the sham-modern Hegel, “not only is space not the negation of reason, it provides place for reason and the idea; space is the first sphere of reason,” since where there is no spatial being apart, there is also no logical being apart.” The distinction between one thing and another can only be perceived sensually if space exists between them. Logic, whether classical or Hegelian, collapses without it. This demonstrates that “the laws of reality are also the laws of thought,” not in the Hegelian sense but in the strictly material sense brought to us by the senses. Whereas Hegel supposes that contradictions are overcome by his ‘X plus not-X = X combined, ‘synthesized,’ with not-X, sensual perception enables time to unite such “opposing and contradicting determinations” by identifying the material reality underlying them, as when white paint and black paint combine to make grey paint, or when a human being can feel happy, then sad, form one intention, then the opposite one.
“The new philosophy has…as its principle of cognition and as its subject, not the ego, the absolute, abstract mind, in short, not reason for itself alone, but the real and whole being of man,” who is not the measure of all things, which exist independently of him, but is instead “the measure of reason.” This leads Feuerbach to anticipate a bit of Nietzsche: “Do not think as a thinker, that is, with a faculty torn from the totality of the real human being and isolated for itself,” but “think as a living and real being, as one exposed to the vivifying and refreshing waves of the world’s ocean.” Only if you “think in existence, in the world as a member of it, not in the vacuum of abstraction as a solitary monad, as an absolute monarch, as an indifferent, superworldly God” can “you be sure that your ideas are unities of being and thought.” In another play on Christianity, Feuerbach affirms that “only the truth that became flesh and blood is the truth.” The difference between man and an animal is that human sense perceptions (rather than illusory ideals, which exist only in the mind) are generalizable, universalizable, even as the religious doctrines of Christianity are said, falsely, to be. Animals care only for smells that serve them as particular beings—things that they can eat or dangerous things they must avoid. Man’s sense of smell is ” a sense embracing all kinds of smell; hence it is a freer sense, a sense that can be elevated “to intellectual and scientific acts.” Human senses perceive not only other men but man as such. “Even in thinking and in being a philosopher, I am a man among men,” engaging in “a dialectic between I and thou.” As a result, Feuerbach shuns the “double truth,” the claims of philosophy on the one hand, religion on the other. The new philosophy unifies both in “the philosophy of man,” “tak[ing] the place of religion because it “has the essence of religion within itself.”
The problem with Feuerbach’s vigorously argued materialism is that it begins with the assertion that sense perceptions are all human beings have to begin with, then excludes all other mental phenomena that might not derive from sense perceptions. If human beings had no sense perceptions, would they have no thoughts? Not necessarily. They might be thinkers thinking themselves. This suggests that those who maintain that philosophy cannot refute religion any more than religion can refute philosophy have a point. By closing the minds of young Germans to God, Feuerbach left intelligent but politically inexperienced persons without firm guidance. This ended badly.
Notes
- On the religion of humanity, see “Manent on the Religion of Humanity” on this cite under the category, “Bible Notes.”
- “To the neo-Platonic philosophers…matter—namely, the material and real world in general—is no longer an authority and a reality. Fatherland, family, worldly ties, and good in general, which the ancient peripatetic philosophy still counted as man’s bliss—all these are nothing for the neo-Platonic sage,” who is no longer capable of distinguishing imagination from perception. “That which is imagination and fantasy with the Neo-Platonists was merely rationalized and transformed by Hegel into concepts.” To Neo-Platonists, God is beyond being, beyond mind, beyond any determination; their imitatio Dei is an ecstasy or rapture; their God is in reality the objectification of this psychological state.” For them, “real man became also a mere abstraction without flesh and blood, an allegorical figure of the divine being. Plotinus, at least according to the report of his biographer, was ashamed to have a body.”
Recent Comments