Chantal Delsol: Unjust Justice: Against the Tyranny of International Law. Paul Seaton translation. Wilmington: ISI Books, 2008.
Originally published in Social Science and Modern Society. Volume 45, Number 4, July/August 2009.
What certain European elites and their imitators call justice isn’t really just. According to them, justice consists of a set of legal rights enforced by the International Criminal Court in a world in which wars have become reclassified as ‘police actions.’ A world constabulary gathers up miscreants in order to bring them up on charges before said august tribunal of humane technocrats.
Chantal Delsol understands the attraction of this arrangement to her fellow Europeans. In the past century tyrants in Europe required of their subjects the sacrifice of Isaac, for isn’t the redemption of humanity in acts of class warfare or racial cleansing worth the blood? To prove one’s faith in Lenin or Hitler one needed only to violate moral law and the conscience that perceived it. “The murderous character of the twentieth century emerged from the contest between faith and morality, with faith winning out all too often” (xvi).
Under these circumstances, eliminated by mid-century but re-imagined for the remainder of it by those who lived in the shadow of nuclear weapons, Europeans understandably seek to “establish institutions of international justice” out of “a desire to make ethics or morality everywhere supreme over obedience to a leader or a system,” false gods who will not stay Abraham’s raised hand. Understandable, yes; coherent, no. Delsol unsparingly observes that rules imply ruling, and thus rulers. Permanent international courts and police forces require a de facto international government. The “new version of international law and justice” requires a world government enforcing the laws and saying what justice is. “But does universal justice exist? At what price does one establish it?” (xix)
Such philosophers as Grotius and Vattel presented the old version of international law and justice. This consisted partly of natural right—rights inhering in human beings as such—discovered and argued for by those philosophers; it also consisted partly of international customs and conventions asserted, negotiated, agreed upon by self-governed societies or states. The old international law resulted, therefore, from politics in the strict sense.
By politics in the strict sense Delsol has Aristotle in mind, and it is one of Delsol’s conspicuous merits as a political philosopher that Aristotle is never far from her mind. To see what she’s thinking, recall the account of the kinds of rule Aristotle describes at the beginning of the Politics. Human families exhibit three kinds of rule: the rule of masters over slaves; the rule of parents over children; and the mutual or reciprocal rule between husbands and wives. Although masterly and parental rule differ sharply because the first benefits ruler more than ruled, whereas the second properly benefits the children who are ruled, both center on command and obedience. Even in those benighted antique times before feminism’s blessed advent, marital rule proceeded by reciprocity, discussion, compromise—in “ruling and being ruled.” Among the several regime possibilities available to citizens in the polis, the politeia or “mixed regime” best addresses the political problem, as it takes this lesson from the family and brings it to public life. The mixed regime requires the few who are rich and the many who are poor to talk with one another before deciding on policy, to treat one another as human beings, as beings capable of reasoning and speech.
The old international law did this, too. Without establishing a world government or regime, international law established a civilized framework for talking and even for fighting. Each state retained its self-rule and therefore (so to speak) its moral integrity. The old international law provided some degree of justice—rough justice, to be sure, itself often violated. But its proponents understood politics and appreciated the place of political life as the architecture of any genuinely human life. The Bible teaches this, too; God lets His prophets talk back, and sometimes He changes His mind after they do.
The new international law, by contrast, finds its model not in the family or the polis or even in the ancient empires (which permitted, largely because they had to, considerable scope for provincial self-government). The new international law finds its model in the modern state. As conceived by Machiavelli, elaborated by Hobbes, and organized by the likes of Henry VIII and Cardinal Richelieu, the rulers of the state incline toward ‘commanding’ rule not political rule, administration not discussion. That the state is not entirely a bad thing may be seen in some societies where it does not exist—Iraq after the years right after the fall of Saddam Hussein, effected by the arrival of Americans who wanted to change the regime without quite appreciating what a regime is. That the state too often can be malign may be seen where it looms all too large—Iraq before Saddam fell, before Americans had arrived. The grandeur and misery of the modern state is the theme of Tocqueville, another of Delsol’s familiars. Tocqueville would preserve politics within statism, as did the American Founders before him; hence Tocqueville’s praise of the American solution, which he calls governmental centralization without administrative centralization, and which James Madison calls extended and federal republicanism.
Although it seems that any international law must cut across states, dilute their sovereignty, this does not necessarily mean that the ‘statist’ model disappears altogether. Advocates of the new international law would “establish a worldwide reign of justice by means of global tribunals, without any possibility of appeal” (5). These advocates prefer not to admit (perhaps even to themselves, although I doubt that) that their project does not transcend the perennial questions of states and regimes but reproduces it on a grand scale. To make this form of legalism work internationally, lawgivers and judges will be necessary. The new internationalists claim that the characteristic feature of modern statism, the princely executive, will no longer tyrannize. But while the rule of the few (namely the lawyers) worries one less than the rule of the tyrannical one, might it not institute the other kind of despotism Tocqueville fears, “soft” despotism? Soft despotism would relieve human beings of politics, relieve them not of their humanity, which endures, but of the exercise of their humanity, the full expression of our nature as homo rationalis et civilis.
Political reason and civility differ from scientific reason and administration. To think again of the family, one ordinarily prefers the intimacy of talk between husband and wife to the therapeutic interventions of the marriage counselor; the counselor knows more about marriage, but the husband and wife know more about their marriage, about one another. In politics, “do we have to castigate the Cambodians, if they decide not to prosecute Pol Pot’s thugs?” (23). Maybe the larger justice of a reconciled society will benefit Cambodians more than exact justice done to each person. This is not moral relativism; it is prudence, and prudence serves justice at least as well as law, which characteristically requires that one size fits all Such unreasonable rationality obliges us to attempt unjust justice. “In order to make [the search for a world state] go away, human beings—all of them—will have to be truly reasonable, and not merely rational” (36).
“It is therefore rather curious to observe Europeans declaim against the Manicheanism of the United States” (41). Not only is the pot calling the kettle black, but the kettle, with its Wilsonian soot removed, turns out not to have been black. The Founders wrote, “We hold these truths to be self-evident.” They did not imagine that George III saw those truths so clearly; nor did they suppose that Europeans could exchange their kings and parliaments overnight. The Americans said that governments derived their just powers from the consent of those the laws govern. Delsol observes: “Every positive law is rooted in a culture. Therefore, in order to have a world law there must be a world culture. There is no such thing. (49) By “world culture” internationalists mean the Davos culture, Samuel P. Huntington’s phrase for the mindset of the ‘globalist’ business executives, politicians, and academics convened annually by the World Economic Forum in Davos, Switzerland. The world is not ready for the rule of such men because the world has yet no taste for their wine, their brie. Delsol recalls Aristotle’s critique of Plato’s regime of philosophers; such a regime would reduce a theme to a single beat. One might add, George Soros is no philosopher-king.
This does not commit Delsol, foolishly, to a rejection of the idea of just war, or of the policy of regime change imposed a peace settlement after such a war. “Contrary to what one might first think, the Americans’ treatment of Iraq—their invasion of Iraq—is more defensible than what Westerners did to Serbia.” Americans judged the Iraqi regime dangerous to themselves. Europeans judged the Milosevic tyranny dangerous not to themselves but to Serbians, yet “conducted a police operation aimed at the elimination of a criminal” (69). Milosevic was a criminal amongst Serbians, not amongst Europeans generally.
In her preceding book, The Unlearned Lessons of the Twentieth Century, Delsol identified a contradiction at the core of contemporary European thought. Against genocide, tyranny, and war, Europeans wanted to uphold human dignity and rights. But against the hyper-Enlightenment ideologies of scientific socialism and race science they deployed a radical skepticism that denied the existence of the modern ‘self’ that had murdered, tyrannized, and made war. They denied the self without returning to the older notion of the soul. Without a soul, or at least a self, in what does human dignity and rights inhere? Europeans fell into soft nihilism, materialism, and pantheism—what Tocqueville had identified as the perils of social democracy when it abandons belief in anything above democrats. But, as she argues in Unjust Justice, “it really is great hubris to believe that a human law or institution”—particularly one constructed from such dispirited elements as the leveling impulse provides—”could be so universal and so perfect that no one confronted by it could appeal to a higher law” (95). Tocqueville predicted that social democracy could end in either of two regimes, republicanism or despotism. World government would be no republic but a vast web of administration, a “world moral authority,” a Sanhedrin without God or the laws of nature’s God, whose morality would incline toward the low but whose power would brook no contradiction.
Let us say, mirabile dictu, that Europeans converted to Christianity or (in a sense more ambitiously still) to Stoicism. St. Paul and Seneca agree that the human race is one thing, not a set of different species. This ontological unity did not imply political unity—except, in Paul’s understanding under the rule of Jesus Christ under a new heaven and on a new earth. Those who would transform ontological unity into political unity on this old earth commit a category mistake, Delsol argues. To “immanentize a spiritual good” (105) is to replace the Holy Spirit with the Absolute Spirit, as Hegel does; contemporary ‘post-moderns’ would do so even while rejecting the high modernism Hegel exemplifies. And even Hegel, it should be noted, has the sense to see that his world eschaton will never be immanentized through courts, but only on history’s slaughter-bench, war. Today’s internationalists want a peaceful, deductive immanence instead of the dialectical immanence Hegel (and before him, Kant) expected. They hope that humanity has already survived the Kantian/Hegelian slaughter-bench, so active in the first half of the twentieth century. This speaks well for their humanitarianism; it may speak more of their sentimentality.
And if they are right about the slaughter-bench, if the wars of the previous century somehow have already brought us to history’s much-anticipated end? If the world state is just around the corner, anticipated by the current congeries of international institutions, whether economic or civil-social? “We no longer have the excuse of ignorance to think that because it embodies the highest morality a world government will produce a miraculous synthesis of total power and good government” (128).
Recent Comments