Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality among Men. In Victor Gourevich, editor and translator: Rousseau: The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
In his First and Second Discourses, Rousseau praises one ‘ancient’ thinker, Socrates, while condemning one set of them, the pre-Socratics. He praises one Christian, Jesus, while condemning one set of Christians, the Scholastics. Among the ‘moderns’ he praises Bacon, Descartes, and Newton while condemning Voltaire, the man Voltaire praises as le sage Locke, and Locke’s predecessor, Hobbes. Among the ancient regimes, he singles out Sparta for praise among the ‘ancients,’ Switzerland among the ‘moderns.’ He proceeds to navigate his argument among these lighthouses, and although he, like Locke, raises self-contradiction to the level of a literary technique, his argument sails carefully through dangerous waters. He wants to confuse some who would track his vessel but always knows where he wants to go, and how to get there.
The First Discourse responds to a question proposed by the Academy of Dijon in a contest it sponsored in 1750: “Has the reestablishment of the sciences and the arts contributed to the purification of moeurs?” No, just the opposite, Rousseau famously replies. Enlightenment leads to “the fatal inequality introduced among men by the distinction of talents and the disparagement of virtues.” In defending this claim he alludes to and quotes Socrates. He takes a Socratic pose, calling himself “an honest man who knows nothing” and quotes Socrates’ criticism of people who believe they know something but really know nothing, whereas he, Socrates, knows he knows nothing—and that is his wisdom. Glancing not only at Socratic self-knowledge but at Cartesian self-examination, he calls the effort “to return into [oneself], there to study man and to know his nature, his duties, and his end” a grander project that the modern Enlightenment. Hence his criticism of the arch-Enlightener, Voltaire. In the essay’s central paragraph he cites Socrates’ opposition to unnamed pre-Socratics, proponents of the Sophistic Enlightenment, “those artful and subtle Greeks who seduced virtue and enervated the courage of his fellow citizens.” Initially, he suggests that among us ‘moderns,’ Socrates would not have drunk hemlock but he would have drunk scorn. In a later footnote he revises this judgment, suspecting that even in ‘enlightened’ times and regimes Socrates would be killed.
What goes for philosophy goes for religion, too. Virtue is “the sublime science of simple souls,” “engraved in all hearts” and therefore conducive to equality. Jesus teaches pure morals; the Scholastics obscure the simplicity of His teachings with their elaborate argumentation. The problem comes back to the misuse of philosophy. Genuine philosophers, thinkers of the stature of Bacon, Descartes, and Newton, need no guides; they teach themselves. Once philosophers or would-be philosophers attempt to flatter the people by giving them reason to suppose they have become ‘enlightened,’ then the esteem for talent begins to replace the esteem for virtues. The people begin to imagine that they are sophisticated. And they are, in the literal sense: transformed into sophists. “It is good that there be Philosophers provided the People do not pretend to be Philosophers.” There is a place for egalitarianism, but the life of the mind isn’t it. Enlightenment amounts to a sort of drug, whereby talented men boost themselves into positions of authority by pretending that they have assisted the people in becoming wise. In fact they have satisfied and stupefied them, the better to rule them.
Hence his praise of Geneva in the Epistle Dedicatory of the Second Discourse. Geneva, he tells the Genevans, has rightly combined natural, moral equality with institutional inequality of talents “in the means most clearly approximating natural law” and “most favorable to society, to the preservation of public order, and the happiness of individuals” by instituting representative government. Representative government ensures that the people themselves don’t administer the (long-established) laws—a task for the talented—while keeping the administrators on the short leash of annual elections. Thus simple souls, wise in the sublime science, monitor the virtue of magistrates, wise in the ways of the world. As for Geneva’s “amiable and virtuous Citizen-women,” they rightly confine themselves to their household, where their “chaste power” is “exercised in conjugal union alone,” and not in the public square. Since “it will always be the lot” of women to rule men, such women as the Genevans will rule in modernity as Spartan women ruled in antiquity, “despis[ing] vain luxury,” loving the laws, and “correct[ing] the misconceptions which our young Men acquire in other countries” that run counter to the “august freedom” Genevans enjoy at home.
In his preface, Rousseau recurs to the ‘Socratic turn’ away from the direct study of nature and from sophistry, the preeminent features of Enlightenment ‘ancient’ and ‘modern’: “The most useful and the least advanced of all human knowledge seems to be that of man” and, like Socrates, he will heed “the inscription on the Temple at Delphi,” which adjured its readers, “Know thyself.” The question proposed by the Academy at Dijon is: “What is the origin of inequality among men, and whether it is authorized by the natural law.” This seems to point essayists to a historical account, but Rousseau asks a preliminary question: “How can the source of inequality among men be known without first knowing men themselves?” To answer this question, not history but introspection is necessary because the human soul has been “altered” in “the lap of society,” altered so much as to have become “almost unrecognizable,” altered so much that “man’s constitution” has changed. Modern souls are no longer simple; progress makes us ignorant of ourselves. Such progress in artful knowledge is by no means necessary; Rousseau rejects teleology, natural or historical, because he sees that some human populations have ‘progressed’ in the sciences and the arts whereas some have not. Only the Socratic way of self-knowledge and the Cartesian ‘method’ of introspection can clear away the crust of conventions and habits but more, show us how the constitution of man itself has changed. Only self-knowledge can ‘recover’ the sense of human nature as it is by nature, which for Rousseau means at its origin and not at its end.
Rousseau emphasizes the non-historical character of his inquiry. “It is no light undertaking to disentangle what is original from what is artificial in man’s present Nature, and to know accurately a state which no longer exists, which perhaps never did exist, which probably never will exist, and about which it is nevertheless necessary to have exact Notions in order accurately to judge of our present state.” Unlike Hobbes and Locke, for whom the state of nature has existed, sometimes still exists, and always will exist (at times), Rousseau rules out empirical evidence from the core of his thinking; in this he anticipates Kant. At the same time, he will not abandon scientific method, the method of Bacon, insofar as it disciplines thought by experiment. Rousseau asks, “What experiments would be needed in order to come to know natural man; and by what means can these experiments be performed within society?” He cedes nothing to the Enlightenment, in that. In the central paragraphs of his preface he charges, as he had in the First Discourse, that some ‘ancients’ and ‘moderns’ have erred in making knowledge of natural law too abstruse; “for it to be natural, it must speak immediately with the voice of Nature.” “Hence, disregarding all the scientific books that only teach us to see men as they have made themselves, and meditating on the first and simplest operations of the human Soul”—as did Descartes and indeed Locke, before him—I believe I perceive in it two principles prior to reason.” One “interests us intensely in our well-being and our self-preservation,” the other “inspires in us a natural repugnance at seeing any sentient Being, and especially any being like ourselves, perish or suffer.” The first principle is identical to that asserted by Hobbes and Locke; the second, pity, amounts to a ‘secularized’ (actually naturalized) version of Christian agape or charity. He endorses the teaching of Hobbes and rejects that of Locke in calling sociability unnatural to man, but unlike Hobbes he tempers this with the sentiment of pity.
“This way one is not obliged to make a Philosopher of man before making a man of him.” Making a man out of man makes man a beast insofar as he shares sentience with other beasts; further, being sentient, both beasts and man partake in natural right. One “must at least give the beast the right not to be uselessly maltreated by man.” The ‘animal rights movement’ begins with Rousseau. Natural law and natural right are simple and comprehensive. “As long as [man] does not resist the internal impulsion of commiseration, he will never harm another man or even any sentient being, except in the legitimate case when, his preservation being involved, he is obliged to give himself preference.” We fail to see this only because arts and sciences have over-complicated our way of life, denaturing man, and especially modern man.
Rousseau addresses the question of the origin of inequality more squarely in his Exordium. Here, he posits a dualism, if not the mind/body dualism of Descartes—that is, Descartes as he is usually taken to claim. There are “two sorts of inequality in the human Species”: natural or physical inequality (“differences of age, health, strengths of Body, and qualities of Mind or of Soul”); and “moral or political inequality,” which depends on “a sort of convention and is established, or at least authorized by Men’s consent.” Rousseau, then, is no less a materialist than Hobbes or Locke and, like them, does not regard human beings as political animals by nature. The precise issue, on these terms, is when Right replaced violence, when Nature was subjected to Law, when the strong resolved to serve the weak, when the people purchased “the idea of repose at the price of real felicity.” No philosopher has yet reached “the state of Nature” because none has begun as Rousseau does, “by setting aside all the facts”; facts “do not affect the question.” Rousseau begins not with facts but with a hypothesis in what we now would call a ‘thought experiment.’ This experiment will have no recourse to revelation, either, but rather to “what Mankind might have become if it had been abandoned to itself,” with no Serpent and no God (at least, no God after Creation). Rousseau insists on this because nature “never lies,” inasmuch as it never speaks, as gods, men, and serpents do.
Part I of the Second Discourse initiates the experiment consideration on the body of man. Rousseau won’t try to trace man’s physical development, which would entangle him in facticity. “Stripping” man of his supernatural, God-made aspects, and of his artificial, man-made aspects, Rousseau finds “an animal,” “the most advantageously organized of all animals.” This animal “perhaps” has no instincts, and so will feed on anything. It ate the fruits and vegetables supplied by an earth that was much more fertile than it is now, and “since prey is almost the only object about which Carnivores fight, and Frugivores live in constant peace with one another, it is clear that if the human species were of the latter kind, tit would have subsisted more easily in the state of Nature, and would have had much less need and fewer occasions to leave it.” The state of nature was neither Hobbes’s war of all against all nor Locke’s condition of scarcity. It was peaceful and abundant.
The state of nature had a ‘regime.’ Nature dealt with early men “exactly as the Law of Sparta did with the Children of Citizens; it makes those who have a good constitution strong and robust, and causes all the others to perish; differing, in this, from our societies, where the State kills children indiscriminately before their birth by making them a burden to their Fathers.” There was no abortion in the state of nature; the right to self-preservation began before birth. Without tools other than his own body, natural man had no weapons other than that. Accordingly, he was stronger and more agile than men today, “ever ready for every eventuality” and largely self-sufficient, carrying “all of [him]self along with [him].” Indeed, he soon finds that he surpasses all the other animals “in skill more than they do him in strength”; he does not live in terror, as Hobbesian natural man does. Without any formidable natural enemies and therefore no fear of violent death, he has no fear of a peaceful death, either. Natural men “eventually die without anyone’s noticing that they cease to be, and almost without noticing themselves.” Their life is solitary, but not nasty, poor, brutish—except in a good way—or short.
This is “the simple, uniform and solitary way of life,” the regime, “prescribed to us by Nature.” It is noteworthy that Rousseau’s claim about man to some extent follows from his method; philosophic introspection focuses the mind on the individual and, sure enough, it finds natural man living alone. Moving away from the body, Rousseau argues that this method is nonetheless necessary now to understand man as he existed then. True, “the state of reflection is a state against nature,” and “the man who meditates” is “a depraved animal”—no longer a machine-like being whose life consists of feeding, attacking, and defending, of simple willing and not willing, desiring and fearing. “Man in the state of Nature” is healthy, simple. But to rediscover him, philosophers—the most meditative, the most depraved of civilized men—can only as it were ‘double down’ on their depravity, use it to get beyond it, at least in their theorizing.
Like all animals, men “lose half” of their “vigor, strength, and courage” when domesticated; as man becomes “sociable and a Slave, he becomes weak, timorous, groveling, and his soft and effeminate way of life completes the enervation of both his strength and his courage.” Worse, because man has it in him to put other domesticated animal species into his own service, and to invent “conveniences” that sap his strength even more than mere domestication alone would do, civilized man has degenerated even more than other animals. Hobbes and Locke are dead wrong; civil society doesn’t secure natural rights, it compromises them. Machiavelli is right to say that Christian religiosity effeminates man, but so do all the trappings of civilized life. The human senses themselves have become denatured. Living in conditions of hardiness, natural man’s “touch and taste will be extremely crude”—these senses “are perfected only by softness and sensuality,” neither of which prevail in nature—but “his sight, hearing and smell” are “most subtle,” as seen in primitive peoples today. Machiavelli’s ‘epistemology’ of touch is therefore an excrescence of civilization, a realism only in unnatural, civil, society.
Moving from physical man to “the Metaphysical and Moral side,” Rousseau sees “in any animal nothing but an ingenious machine to which nature has given senses in order to wind itself up and to a point, protect itself against everything that tends to destroy or to disturb it.” So too with natural man, “with this difference”: “man contributes to his operations in his capacity as a free agent,” a being that “chooses or rejects” freely, not by instinct alone. “As a result the Beast cannot deviate from the Rule prescribed to it even when it would be to its advantage to do so, while man often deviates from it to his detriment.” In man, “the Mind depraves the senses, and the will continues to speak when Nature is silent.” It isn’t the capacity to reason that differentiates human beings from other animals; reasoning is unnatural. “It is his property of being a free agent” that differentiates him, “and it is mainly in the consciousness of this freedom that the spirituality of his soul exhibits itself.” That is, in examining himself, Rousseau finds not only man’s original physical attributes but also consciousness of his own freedom. The emphasis on “consciousness” seen in subsequent thinkers starts here. It can be seen even today in the valorizing slang term, ‘woke,’ and it has been esteemed by thinkers from Hegel and Marx to contemporary feminists and libertarians, who make ‘choice’ a ‘value’ in itself. Here is a more nearly Cartesian kind of dualism. Rousseau needs something along these lines because nature is not teleological, in his theory; finding un-mechanical dimensions in himself, he explains them in terms of the power of choosing, “and in the sentiment of this power”—”purely spiritual acts about which nothing is explained by the Laws of Mechanics.”
Even more teleological, without being a natural teleology in (for example) Aristotle’s sense is a related natural power of human being, its “faculty of perfecting itself.” This power typically leads man not to the flowering of his best potential; quite on the contrary. “It would be sad for us to be forced to agree that this distinctive and almost unlimited faculty is the source of all of man’s miseries; that it is the faculty which, by dint of time, draws him out of that original condition in which he would spend calm and innocent days; that it is the faculty which, over the centuries, causes his enlightenment, and his errors, his vice and his virtues to arise, and eventually makes him his own and Nature’s tyrant.” Sad, but true. His labor and sciences only “feed his insane pride and I know not what vast self-admiration.” While man— by nature solitary, peaceful, vigorous, and content—”is naturally good,” men—living under civil-social conditions but retaining their essentially solitary, ‘individual’ characteristic (if nothing else)—”are wicked.” Such creatures, living socially, bump up against each other, moving themselves “to hate one another in proportion as their interests cross.” Society consists of a collection of such individuals, whose natural traits, harmless when living in natural isolation, become lethal in close quarters. They see “how one man’s loss almost always makes for another’s prosperity,” and “more dangerous still,” how “public calamities” offer opportunities for private gain and are therefore “waited and hoped for by a host of private individuals,” who never let a ‘good crisis’ go to waste. In civil society, Machiavelli is more nearly right than Hobbes or Locke, inasmuch as “men are forced to flatter and destroy one another” there.
“Savage man, once he has supped, is at peace with all of Nature and a friend to all of his kind.” Asocial, and therefore with no sacred honor to defend, and indeed no sense of either the sacred or of pride to inspire such a sentiment, his fights over food will be brief, “end[ing] with a few fisticuffs”; “the victor eats, the vanquished goes off to seek his fortune.” Not so with “man in Society,” where the passions for luxury, distinction, and mastery feed on one another, and “my Hero will end up by cutting every throat until he is the sole master of the Universe”in his quest to satisfy “the secret aspirations of the heart of every Civilized man.” In effect, civilized man dreams of returning to his original, natural solitude, but now spurred by libido dominandi at the service of supreme vanity. International and civil war, piracy, crime, abortion, infanticide, join with such lesser evils as miserable marriages, unhealthy occupations, and luxury to make civil society anything but civil. “As industry and the arts spread and flourish, the scorned farmer, weighed down by taxes needed to support Luxury, and condemned to spend his life between labor and hunger, abandons his fields to go look in the Cities for the bread which he should be bringing there,” resulting in the modern state which “on one side grows rich, grows weak and is depopulated on the other,” soon “the prey of the poor Nations that succumb to the fatal temptation to invade them,” growing “rich and weak in their turn, until they are themselves invaded and destroyed by others.” To complete the horrors, civilized man cannot return to nature; only religion is left to him. Alone among the civilized, a philosopher might rediscover a natural way of life, as Rousseau himself did, becoming the solitary walker, in but not of modern society. The solitary walker communes not with God; he is the restless desert saint of the self.
How can such rare souls establish such a way of life for themselves? In Rousseau there is no philo-sophia, no intellectual eros striving for noetic satisfaction. “Human understanding owes much to the Passions”; “it is by their activity that our reason perfects itself,” as “we seek to know only because we desire to enjoy.” “The Passions, in turn, owe their origin to our needs and their progress to our knowledge.” The only goods Savage man knows are “food, a female, and rest; the only evils he fears are pain, and hunger”—not death, as Hobbes supposes, “for an animal will never know what it is to die.” As savages interact with circumstances, they will respond with different ways of satisfying these modest goods and avoiding or ameliorating these evils. The arts—and therefore civilization—first arose in Egypt because the cyclical flooding of the Nile River forced savages to invent in order to survive. Egypt turned out to be the exception to a general rule: “the peoples of the North are more industrious than those of the south because they can less afford not to be so, as if Nature wanted in this way to equalize things, by endowing Minds with the fertility it denies the Soil.”
If so, and if the path to civilization widens and lengthens in the manner Rousseau sketches, only a few men will resist the decadence. They will do so by means of Rousseau’s version of Cartesian introspection, beginning by taking measure of “the distance between pure sensations and the simplest knowledge.” They will then be in the intellectual position to ask themselves, “How many centuries perhaps elapsed before men were in a position to see any other fire than that of Heaven? How many different chance occurrences must they have needed before they learned the most common uses of this element?” Such men will ask themselves how a non-rational animal could develop the language that was necessary before the principle of non-contradiction could be discovered. How long did it take before the random sexual reproduction seen in nature led to the institution of the family? In nature, mothers initially nursed their infants only to relieve their own discomfort, and then out of habit-induced love of their own. Even as Hobbes is wrong about the state of nature as the state of war, Locke is wrong about conjugal society. Why would a man stick around to assist in providing for his mate or his children? (Rousseau well knows that many don’t want to do that, even now.) “There is, therefore, no reason for the man to seek out the same woman, nor for the woman to seek out the same man. Locke’s argument collapses.”
As for language, the centerpiece of the classical philosophic understanding of man as the being of logos, of speech and reason, and equally the centerpiece of Biblical creationism, Rousseau addresses it in the Discourse‘s central paragraph. “Man’s first language, the most universal, the most energetic and the only language he needed before it was necessary to persuade assembled men, is the cry of Nature,” a cry “wrested from him only by a sort of instinct on urgent occasions,” never in the ordinary course of his life. Accordingly, savage man had no ideas. Contra the Book of Genesis, “Each object was at first given a particular name without regard to kinds and species”—one oak was called Ed, another Ralph. Or something like that. Locke’s “general ideas can enter the Mind only with the help of words,” and the only natural language consisted of cries of passion in extremis and, eventually, names assigned to particular objects. A simple thought experiment will relieve you of any other notion: “Only the definition of a Triangle gives you its genuine idea; as soon as you [frame the] figure [of] one in your mind, it is some one given Triangle and not another.” Ideas and the abstract or generalized word arose “by means which I cannot conceive.” Philosophic inquiry stops here.
But philosophic inquiry does give the rare soul a glimpse of what the natural life for man was. Asocial natural man was “a free being whose heart is at peace and body in health,” not the miserable being imagined by Hobbes and Locke. Savage man never commits suicide; he was not so much beyond good and evil as prior to those conditions, “neither good nor wicked.” In this, the Bible is right, if for the wrong reasons. (Here, one should notice, Rousseau revises his previous claim that natural man was good.) “In instinct alone he had all he needed to live in the state of Nature,” whereas—and here he speaks to the rare souls—”in cultivated reason he was only what he needs to live in society.” What savage man knew by natural instinct, the philosopher can re-learn by the right use of reason—beginning with introspection.
Introspecting further, Rousseau finds another sentiment in savage man. Human self-love, amour de soi, aims at self-preservation. So much Hobbes and Locke saw. But further, “self-preservation prior to the birth of vanity”—amour-propre—”tempers his ardor for well-being”—that is, a life beyond the satisfaction of physical necessity—”with an innate repugnance to see his kind suffer.” This is “the force of natural pity,” a pure movement of Nature prior to all reflection,” a sentiment that causes savage man to “identify” with suffering fellow-humans. Pity predates the Golden Rule and is “perhaps more useful”; “the first sentiment of humanity,” it is the source of all “social virtues” today, leading us to the maxim, “Do your good with the least possible harm to others.”
This raises a serious problem. How could savage man feel repugnance at the sufferings of his kind if he couldn’t recognize species, if he had no power of abstraction? If George sees that Oglethorpe in pain, what is it to George? Rousseau does not ask himself that question, here.
Instead, he considers reason and the philosophy it underpins. These isolate man within civil society. Reason “turns man back upon himself,” as it does for Descartes and for Rousseau. In this it reestablishes certain men in something close to man’s natural condition. But “although Socrates and Minds of his stamp may be capable of acquiring virtue through reason, Mankind would long ago have ceased to be if its preservation depended solely on the reasonings of those who make it up.” If reason originates under social conditions, if deployed socially in projects for the general ‘enlightenment’ of whole societies, it merely serves vanity, amour-propre. If used introspectively, however, it can turn away from the vanities of civil society, back toward the rediscovery of human nature, abandoning the sorrows that will soon torment Young Werther, the soul-agonies of civilized man. Sexual passion, for example, will redirect itself. Natural, physical love is fleeting and harmless, serving to preserve the species without knowing it does so. “Any woman suits” savage man; there were no epic wars over a Helen in the state of nature. Moral love, however, “gives this desire its distinctive character and focuses it exclusively on a single object,” a “factitious sentiment” leading young men to submit to the tyranny of women, who extol moral love “in order to establish their rule and to make dominant the sex that should obey.” When man was always free to move on from his current mate, there could be no conflicts over women, a condition which “renders vain the Law of the stronger.” Even under the conditions of decadence prevailing in civil life, the philosopher will discover this, and begin to live according to the natural standard insofar as prudence enables him to negotiate his way through the artificial reefs and shoals of society.
“It remains for me to consider and bring together the various contingencies that can have perfected human reason while deteriorating the species, make a being wicked by making it sociable, and from so remote a beginning finally bring man and the world to the point where we now find them.” This is his task in Part II. There he turns to the ‘historical’ account he had eschewed earlier, but this can now be a story decisively inflected by his experiment in philosophic introspection. Rousseau offers the sort of history of inequality’s origins that the essay topic implies, but it is a philosophic history.
Whatever beginnings language and other social relations may have had prior to the event, “the first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, to whom it occurred to say this is mine and found people sufficiently simple to believe him, was the true founder of civil society” and therefore the origin of inequality among men. What had happened between the state of nature and the idea of property, bringing human beings to this point?
“Man’s first sentiment was that of his existence, his first care that of his preservation.” (This is the experience the philosopher seeks to recreate, as it were, in the Reveries.) “The earth’s products provided him with all the assistance he needed, instinct moved him to use them”—a “blind inclination, devoid of any sentiment of the heart,” led to reproduction, after which “the two sexes no longer recognized one another, and even the child no longer meant anything to the Mother as soon as it could do without her.” In defending himself against his few natural enemies, savage man used “natural weapons” (stones, branches), “learn[ing] to overcome the obstacles of Nature.” As the human population grew, “difficulties multiplied” along with it. Necessity being the mother of invention, “they invented line and hook,” becoming “fishermen and Fish-eaters.” “Lightning, a Volcano, or some happy accident acquainted them with fire a new resource against the rigors of winter”; once they learned to conserve and to reproduce fire, savage man began “to prepare the meats they had previously devoured raw.” Crucially, “this repeated interaction of the various beings with himself as well as with one another must naturally have engendered in man’s mind perceptions of certain relationships,” such as those “we express by the words, great, small, strong, weak, fast, slow, fearful, bold, and other such ideas, compared as need required and almost without thinking about it, finally produced in him some sort of reflection, or rather a mechanical prudence that suggested to him the precautions most necessary for his safety.” This was the first “enlightenment,” as man “became the master of those [animals] that could be useful, and the scourge of those that could be harmful to him.” At the same time, he must have begun to recognize his similarity to some of those animals, enabling him to take the next step of association with them.
“Taught by experience that love of well-being is the sole spring of human actions, he was in a position to distinguish between the rare occasions when common interest should make him count on the help of his kind, and the even rarer occasions when competition should make him suspicious of them.” He “united with them in a herd, or at most in some kind of free association that obligated no one and lasted only as long as the transitory need that had formed it”; at other times, “everyone sought to seize his own advantage” by force or by fraud, depending upon whether he had an advantage of physical or mental strength. For this level of cooperation he needed no more language than the cries, gestures, and imitative noises we see in other ‘social’ animals, such as crows and monkeys.
Such free associations, if transient, eventually led to “a first revolution”: “the establishment and differentiation of families” along with some sort of property, “from which perhaps a good many quarrels and Fights already arose.” Conjugal and paternal love—amour de soi under changed circumstances—could now exist, but with it, and property, came leisure and the degeneration of man’s natural hardiness. From families came nations, “united in morals and character, not by Rules or Laws.” Familial and ultimately family rivalries, including jealousy, flowed from this newly-complex version of self-love. Cain and Abel, yes, but they were competing for the favor of some woman, not God. “The moment men needed the help of another” to satisfy their newly-real but artificial needs “equality disappeared, property oppressed, work became necessary”—Rousseau’s understanding of the curse of Adam resulted not in death, which had existed all along, but “slavery and misery.”
“Everyone began to look at everyone else and to wish to be looked at himself, and public esteem acquired a value.” Who sings or dances best? Who is “the handsomest, the strongest, the most skillful, or the most eloquent”? Hence vanity and contempt, shame and envy, inequality and vice—in a word, civil society, the earliest versions of which Hobbes and Locke mistook for the state of nature. “All subsequent progress has been so many steps in appearance toward the perfection of the individual”—deluded by amour-propre —”and in effect toward the decrepitude of the species.” No wonder that the few remaining savages today resist our “civilizing missions.” “Metallurgy and agriculture were the two arts the invention of which brought about this great revolution. For the Poet it is gold and silver; but for the Philosopher it is iron and wheat that civilized men, and ruined Mankind.” This explains Europe’s advantage over other parts of the world, as it “is both the most abundant in iron and the most fertile in wheat.”
Once some men began to melt and forge iron, others were needed to feed them. The invention of the plow brought metallurgy and agriculture together; division of land followed, itself followed by the need for “the first rules of justice” designed to stabilize property ownership. With this, conventional right supplanted the natural law. More, the primitive capacities to hunt and to gather take little ability, but farming and metallurgy do. This made certain natural capacities the basis for ever-increasing civil-social inequality. Under these conditions, if you don’t have much natural ability, you fake it until you make it. “To be and to appear became two entirely different things, and from this distinction arose ostentatious display, deceitful cunning, and all the ices that follow in their train,” including “consuming ambition, the ardent desire to raise one’s relative fortune less out of genuine need than in order to place oneself above others.” “All these evils are the first effect of property, and the inseparable train of nascent inequality.”
The war of all against all that resulted induced men for form social contracts to “protect and defend all the members of the association, repulse common enemies, and keep us in eternal concord.” Or so the first ‘founder’ told his dupes, who then “ran toward their chains in the belief that they were securing their freedom,” chains with which “gave the weak new fetters and the rich new forces, irreversibly destroy[ing] natural freedom, forever.”
Forever: there will be no return. Philosopher can come the closest; civil societies, for their part, may at least redesign their chains in a manner that loosens them, making them citizens instead of slaves of some master. At best, the vast majority of men can only craft “a true Contract between the People and the Chiefs it chooses for itself.” Hence Du Contrat Social. From the first Discourse to the Reveries, each book in Rousseau’s oeuvre has its exact place in the outline provided here, in this book.
These vast changes in human life suggest to Rousseau one of his most influential and (as it proved) dangerous notions. “The Mankind of one age is not the Mankind of another age.” By this, Rousseau doesn’t mean simply that different regimes or ways of life reward some human types and punish others. Human nature itself changes as “original man gradually vanishes.” Whereas “the Savage lives in himself,” man in civil society, “sociable man,” lives “always outside himself, is capable of living only in the opinion of others and, so to speak, derives the sentiment of his existence solely from their judgment.” Sociable men “have nothing more than a deceiving and frivolous exterior, honor without virtue, reason without wisdom, and pleasure without wisdom.”
With human nature deemed malleable, subsequent philosophers, especially under the very different but complementary influence of Hume, would seek the source of right elsewhere, eventually in ‘History’ now reconceived not as the story of the course of events but as the course of events itself. The optimism of the Enlightenment, which Rousseau intended to bridle, would not only return but overwhelm the political sense of limits, of moderation and balance in ways that would magnify the vices of civilization Rousseau deplored.
Recent Comments