Emile Durkheim and Marcel Mauss: Primitive Classification. Rodney Needham translation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967. French original published in 1903.
Denying that logic is natural, by which they mean innate to human beings, the authors claim that their “methods of scientific thought [are] veritable social institutions whose origin sociology alone can retrace and explain.” How, then, does sociology explain itself? And how does it know that its self-explanation, if it has one, is accurate, and how does it know that its explanation of other phenomena, including the methods of scientific thought, are accurate?
The authors are historicists, offering an explanation of scientific method, and especially of scientific classification as “a history,” one moreover with “a considerable prehistory.” According to them, scientific classification is only as old as Aristotle, but before him there existed “primitive classification.” “It would be impossible to exaggerate, in fact, the state of indistinction from which the human mind developed,” and substantial elements of this fuzzy thinking persist, as seen “even today” in “a considerable portion of our popular literature, our myths, and our religions,” founded as they are “in a fundamental confusion of all images and ideas,” as seen in notions of metamorphosis and “the materialization of spirits and the spiritualization of material objects.” “The Christian dogma of transubstantiation is a consequence of this state of mind and may serve to prove its generality.” Other “cultures” still claim that transformation of one thing to another occurs; “the Bororo [for example] sincerely images himself to be a parrot.” In this, “culture” mirrors the development of the individual human mind, which begins with “only a continuous flow of representations which are lost one in another,” and even such distinctions as mature human beings make would remain “quite fragmentary” “if education did not inculcate ways of thinking which it could never have established by its own efforts and which are the result of an entire historical development,” since “every classification implies a hierarchical order for which neither the tangible world nor our mind gives us the model.” If so, if all is ‘social history, how does sociology help? How does it begin? And if classification systems are historically and socially determined, then why is ‘sociology’ not merely another game of thrones? If it is, why should it replace the existing ‘principalities and powers’? Why would that replacement do any good?
Durkheim and Mauss first consider the “primitive” classification systems seen among native Australian peoples. Each tribe has two sections, what the ancient Greeks called phratries and what the authors call “moieties.” Each moiety has clans within in it, and each also has two marriage classes within it. Crucially, “the classification of things reproduces this classification of men,” although it is assumed rather than argued that it isn’t the other way around. For example, alligators constitute one moiety, kangaroos another, although some moieties and some clans may encompass a variety of what we would call animal species. Human and animal moieties intersect, as the totems of a clan within a moiety often corresponds to the animal represented on a totem. “Things attributed to one moiety are clearly separated from those which are attributed to the other; those attributed to different clans of one and the same moiety are no less distinct. But all those which are included in one and the same clan are, in large measure, undifferentiated. They are of the same nature”—the latter being a term brought in from the Greeks, inasmuch as the Australian peoples do not take reality to be stable, predictable; an event such as death, for example, is always attributed to sorcery. Within the tribes, “the social divisions applied to the primitive mass of representations have indeed cut them into a certain number of delimited divisions, but the interior of these divisions has remained in a relatively amorphous state which testifies to the slowness and the difficulty with which the classificatory function has been established.” This leaves one to wonder how the moieties themselves were distinguished, if not by means of some natural human capacity. Indeed, the authors observe that when a group becomes too large it is divided, whether it is a moiety divided into clans and sub-clans or a non-human group. The authors describe this as “a completely logical process,” suggesting an underlying human nature beneath primitive classification. This notwithstanding, while for Western men “the essence of man is his humanity,” “the essence of the Australian is in his totem.”
The totems are closely associated with sorcery, magic. Each totem “confers upon the individuals who belong to it various powers over different kinds of things.” Some of these powers correlate the totem with an animal species, but not necessarily. For example, the people whose totem is a drum may have powers associated with tortoises, but they also have “the right to conduct a ceremony which consists in imitating dogs.”
The same kind of classification prevails in North America, where the Zuñi tribe of the Pueblo people classify tribes by regions but also by the system “we have seen already in Australia.” The phenomenon also may be seen among the Omaha tribe of the Sioux, hundreds of miles further to the north of the Pueblo. Space and totem are related. Two moieties will be seen to “have distinct personalities,” and “because each has a different role in the life of the tribe, they are spatially opposed; one is established on the one side, the other on the other side; one is oriented in one direction, the other in the opposite.” And this prevails not only among the Zuñi and the Omaha but throughout the continent, “among the Iroquois, the Wyandot, the disintegrated Seminole tribe of Florida, the Tlingit, and the Loucheux or Déné Dindjé, the most northern, the most bastardized, but also the most primitive of Indians.” (André Malraux recounts a story told by Carl Jung, who visited one of the North American Indian tribes. When the chief politely inquired what Jung’s totem was, the great social scientist answered that his people, the Swiss, had no totems. When they descended from the pole-supported room they had been meeting in, the chief descended the ladder as Westerners descend a staircase—facing out, while Jung descended as Westerners descend a ladder, facing the ladder. When Jung stood on the ground, the chief silently pointed to the Bear of Berne, embroidered on the back of Jung’s jacket. “The bear is the only animal that descends with its face to a tree trunk—or a ladder.”) What we would call nature is both fluid—susceptible to the manipulations of sorcery—and rigid—classified in accordance with “fixed relationships to equally fixed regions in space.” Moreover, the camp, the region the tribe inhabits, “is the center of the universe, and the whole universe is concentrated within it.” “Cosmic space and tribal space are thus only very imperfectly distinguished, and the mind passes from one to the other without difficulty, almost without being aware of doings so.”
And there is Asia. In China, too, the “classification of regions, seasons, things, and animal species dominates the whole of life.” “It is the very principle of the famous doctrine of gung-shui, and through this it determines the orientation of buildings, the foundation of towns and houses, the siting of toms and cemeteries; if certain tasks are undertaken here and others there, if certain affairs are conducted at such and such a time, this is due to reasons based on this traditional systematization.” “All these infinitely numerous elements are combined to determine the genus and the species of things in nature, the direction of movement of forces, and acts which must be performed, thus giving the impression of a philosophy which is at once subtle and naive, rudimentary and refined.” As for their own ‘philosophy,’ it has a subtlety and a naivete of its own, as the authors find “traces” of social origins of the Chinese classification system but nothing very impressive. They tend to ‘sociologize’ human life, including the life of human minds, without considering the infinite regress this entails, if one contemplates their own enterprise.
The authors do not exclude ancient Western societies from their inquiry. “One cannot but remark that the two principles of Heraclitean Ionism, viz. war and peace, and those of Empedocles, viz. love and strife, divide things between them in the same way as do yang and yin in the Chinese classification,” or that “the relationships established by the Pythagoreans between numbers, elements, sexes, and a certain number of other things are reminiscent of the correspondences of magico-religious origin which we have had occasion to discuss.” The notion of the world “as a vast system of classified and hierarchized sympathies” may be discerned among some characters in the Platonic dialogues.
The authors conclude by noticing a certain continuity between “primitive classifications” and those classifications “employed by more civilized peoples.” The early classifications feature “all the essential characteristics” of those we now have: they are hierarchical, with groups “stand[ing] in fixed relationships to each other,” forming “a single whole”; they have “a purely speculative purpose,” namely “to advance understanding,” not (or at least not only) to “facilitate action.” “Such classifications are thus intended, above all, to connect ideas, to unify knowledge; as such, they may be said without inexactitude to be scientific, and to constitute a first philosophy of nature.” As sociologists, Durkheim and Mauss insist that primitive men were not “divided into clans by a pre-existing classification of things but, on the contrary, they classified things because they were divided by clans.” That is, they are social determinists, albeit social determinists who never explain how they were able to climb from the cave of convention to the bright sunlight of social science.
As proof, they observe that “the first logical categories were social categories; the first classes of things were classes of men, into which the things were integrated.” Really? What about the distinctions between the edible and the inedible, light and dark, hot and cold? “Moieties were the first genera; clans, the first species.” Male and female? They claim that it was “states of the collective soul which gave birth to these groupings,” but this sociocentric explanation of human cognition cannot be the whole account even of “primitive classification.” While it is often true that “the pressure exerted by the group on each of its members does not permit individuals to judge freely the notions which society itself has elaborated,” this would make sociology itself a dubious enterprise. An enterprise, moreover, that inclines to replace moral reasoning with scientific accounts of morality, thereby undermining the societies in which sociologists practice their craft, and indeed possibility of sociology’s intellectual self-immolation.
Recent Comments