Review of Maurice Friedmann: Martin Buber’s Life and Work. Volume I. The Early Years: 1878-1923. New York: E. P. Dutton, 1982.
Earlier version published in Chronicles of Culture, October 1982.
Republished with permission.
Education defines political life more fully than brute power does. Admit that “Of the gods we believe, and of men we know, that by a necessary law of their nature they rule wherever they can.” The real questions remain: Which gods? Which men? Ruling for what purpose? The kind of education they propose for their regime will tell us.
Education reveals purpose not only in subject matter and in doctrine but also in the tension between teacher and student. In tyrannies this tension consists mostly of fear; in democracies, it often consists of egoism and un-platonic eros; the best regime would encourage the loving tension between a genuine teacher and a genuine student. And the genuine teacher, remaining also a genuine student, will feel this tension within himself, too.
Martin Buber seeks knowledge of a personal sort, and he seeks to impart it–or, more accurately, to inspire his readers to seek it. “Going forth” to seek the truth is “unteachable in the sense of prescriptions” although he quickly goes on to prescribe the giving-up of the “false drive for self-affirmation” as a preliminary to this quest. The celebrated and succinct way he puts this is to celebrate the “I-Thou” relationship, not the “I-It” relationship. He regards the impersonal, “I-It” relationship as foundational to the corrupt and lethal utopias that had arisen a century before his birth and flourished virally in his own century. In Paths in Utopia, Buber observes that the decline of religion, the traditional frame of education, did not eliminate dreams of paradise: “the whole force of dispossessed eschatology was converted into utopia at the time of the French revolution,” a utopia Marxists tried to win by conquest–by treating their enemies as things, not as persons. Thus education, religion, and politics each reveals the same problem in a different way. The problem of subject and object confronts teachers and students, gods and men, rulers and ruled, would-be conquerors and supposed slaves.
Maurice Friedmann narrates Buber’s life and work leading to the publication of his best-known book, I and Thou. Although labeled a mystic, Buber was no such thing; Friedmann shows that Buber never undertook mysticism’s project, transcending the world by uniting with God. He respected but finally rejected Hasidism. Buber regarded this world as the place to encounter God. The “I-Thou” means refusing to regard nature, men, and spirit as objects to be owned or used, which is the “I-It” relation. “I-Thou” means the kind of participation with the other that a sentence cannot state but which lovers know. Buber equally rejects Hegel’s idea of the Absolute Spirit, the dialectical unfolding of freedom conceived as ever-increasing human control over the congealed Absolute Spirit that is matter. Such control is a matter of mastery, not reciprocity. But “we live in the currents of universal reciprocity” and not dominance, not any `overcoming’ by means of conflict followed by synthesis. Unlike Hegel or any non-philosophic pantheist, Buber regards God’s immanence not as a fact but as a task yet to be accomplished and perhaps never to be fully accomplished but always to be striven for. This striving must not be erotic/desiring or thumotic/ambitious but patient, a matter of attentive readiness to enter into relations of reciprocity with others, whether they are fellow humans or any other natural beings.
In describing this, Friedmann refuses to let us imagine that Buber’s love partook of sentimentality, let alone eroticism. Sentimental love idealizes its object; erotic love desires to possess it. “I-Thou” love thinks and feels with the other, wants the best for it. It is the love translated as `compassion’ in many English-language versions of the Bible: agape in the Greek, Chesed in Hebrew. Love is not a feeling but a cosmic force, “a responsibility of an I for a Thou.” To be animated by that love inoculated Buber from certain temptations. Friedmann quotes Buber’s recollection of Lou Salomé, the veteran seductress who claimed numerous intellectuals: “Every man fell in love with her, but I didn’t.” If every man does something but I do not, does this make me more than a man? Or less? Buber sanely, wisely, understood the limits of “I-Thou” love as well as its strength: “even love cannot persist in direct relation: it endures but only in the alternation of actuality and latency.” God sustains this love steadily, but Buber never made that claim for himself.
Despite his intellectual prowess, Buber ruled out the love philosophers know, the love of wisdom. He goes so far as to call intellect a “parasite” of nature, contending that reason’s law, the law of non-contradiction, requires the separation that makes the “I-It” inevitable. As Friedmann puts it, “Plato’s logical categories of the same and the other and Aristotle’s logic of A and not-A can never comprehend the simultaneous reality of distancing and relating, separateness and togetherness, arrows going apart and arrows coming together, concrete situation and free response, which make up the meeting of I and thou.” And to those who would reply that that is what the Socratic dialogue, as a conversation between persons, must be intended to illustrate, Buber would say he admires that dialogue but it remains nonetheless dialectical, a dual of `points of view’ and not “an interaction between persons.” Crucially, he admits that he never experienced Plato’s eros for ideas, any more than he lusted for Miss Salomé. This presents a problem. Without the principle of non-contradiction, no one could distinguish the “I-Thou” from the “I-It.” Buber makes that distinction very clearly, but he may have failed to distinguish between the nature of Platonic eros, which longs for wisdom not merely to possess it but to incorporate it into oneself, to become wiser, indeed to participate in what truly is, and the modern or Machiavellian call to (as we continue to say) grasp reality, to possess, control, manipulate, caress or annihilate it.
If Buber often sounds as much Christian as Jewish, it is because in a way he was. “From my youth onward,” he wrote, “I have found in Jesus my great brother.” The “communal immediacy” of early Christianity superseded the legalism of the Judaism that Jesus encountered. Buber never flirted with conversion, however, as he considered true Christianity a revival of true Judaism, and never believed Jesus to be divine. To Buber, the “I-Thou” love forms the core of both religions, and I think he is right about that. The real distinction between Buber and the Bible–both Testaments–and Plato is not so much their manner of loving as the beings loved. For Plato the final reality is nature; except for human nature, nature is not a person. Knowledge therefore mostly aims at intimacy with an `It’ or with many`Its,’ not at intimacy with a Person (or, in polytheism, Persons). Human beings, nature in the form of persons, want to know their place within that natural cosmos. Hence the indispensable value of ideas, of abstractions from the concrete manifestations of reality, abstractions that enable us to see the relations among things of a kind, and among the various kinds of things. The Bible reveals that the ultimate reality is a Person. To know the most important `thing’ is not to know a thing, and therefore not to abstract or generalize among things, but to know this Person, with love.
Friedmann offers a lucid explanation of why Buber expected Biblical love to prevail, why the Word would become flesh in society at large, and not only in the persons of God’s prophets. “Buber’s statement in I and Thou, `In the beginning is the relation,’ is not an alternative to the Johannine `In the beginning was the Word’ but a restoration to it of the biblical dynamic and mutuality of the words as `between.'” By this Friedman means that “the true beginning of relationship is the speech of God which creates the world and addresses man. The world really becomes through God’s word, and the world takes place and becomes real for man in the word. Speech is thus the face-to-face existence of the creatures, and pure creation coincides with pure speaking. That we can Thou is to be understood from the fact that Thou is said to us.” God love us first, Person to person. This is why the Logos of Jerusalem surpasses the logos of Athens, philosophic speech. Buber mistakenly supposes that Socrates wanted his regime-in-speech to come to fruition in practice, but even and perhaps especially if he had seen that Socrates likely intends no such consummation he would prefer God’s kind of speech all the more.
Intensely private, love translates into the realities of public life only with difficulty. Buber rejected the secular-political Zionism of Theodore Herzl because he thought Herzl wanted to `Americanize’ Palestine, make it into a state that defended rights that were human-all-too-human; Herzl was “a whole man, but not a whole Jew.” Buber wanted the land of Israel to become again the land of Judaism. Buber had the courage to try to the translation of love into politics not only `on paper,’ in his writings, but in political practice. I and Thou does not ignore economic and political reality: “Man’s will to profit and will to power are natural and legitimate as long as they are tied to the will to human relations and carried by it…. The statesman or businessman who serves the spirit is no dilettante,” as he tries to define the limits of spirit and will “every day anew, according to the right and measure of that day.” This seems to indicate Buber’s interest in what Plato and the other classical philosophers called phronesis, usually translated in English as `prudence,’ although without the connotation of self-serving calculation it has sometimes acquired.
The thought deserves an example that Buber never gives. But Friedmann steps up to the biographer’s rightful task by supplying one. After World War I, he recounts, Buber resumed the Zionist activities that had involved him (and would continue to involve him) for most of his life. He hoped that Palestinian Jews, practicing the “I-Thou” way of living, could live harmoniously with Palestinian Arabs instead of “turn[ing] them into sworn enemies.” Friedmann sees this as prophetic, for “the situation had not yet polarized… into Zionism and anti-Zionism.”
Given the characteristics of Islam, one may doubt that this polarity was avoidable. Islam forthrightly assigns the status of subordination, dhimmitude, to non-Muslims. Islamic law builds the “I-It” relation into the Muslim’s soul. (Does this follow from the Islamic emphasis on God-as-will, not God-as-love? It might.) Evidently, Buber’s colleagues also had their doubts. At the Twelfth Zionist Congress in 1921, Buber wrote a resolution calling for Arab-Jewish unity in Palestine. It was amended into innocuousness. Friedmann quotes Buber: “My role as a `politician,’ i.e. as a man who takes part in the political activity of a group was finished…. [H]enceforth I would not start anything where I had to choose between the truth as I saw it and what was actually being achieved.” That is exactly the choice that statesmen and businessmen make every day. It requires the prudence that Buber seems to esteem but finally cannot practice. In Buber’s defense, it is true that at some point compromise might go too far; withdrawal might be the only decent recourse, as the American founders thought in declaring their independence.
For Buber, though, withdrawal to what, where? Paths in Utopia ends with praise for the kibbutzim. To what extent could communalists defend themselves against large armies? Buber evidently formed what Tocqueville would have called a civil-social strategy to achieve communalist self-defense. Rather than approaching the problem of peace politically (as, for example, U. S. Secretary of State Thomas Jefferson envisioned when he encouraged the proliferation of commercial-republic regimes in the New World), Buber wanted to “deprive the political principle of its supremacy over the social principle” by encouraging “the resolute will of all peoples to cultivate the territories and raw materials of our planet and govern its inhabitants, together.” But of course if the social principle is to achieve “supremacy” over the political principle, the social principle rules, and thus becomes effectively a new political principle. It can do so, Buber surmises, because politics as ordinarily understood consists of putting things in order, but the fundamental order of the cosmos cannot be put in order because it is already orderly. Communalism would (so to speak) tap into the loving order of reality–align human life with the dynamic and permanent I-Thou. This seems to mean the gradual establishment of kibbutzim under the protective carapaces of actual states, worldwide. And this would require those states to have regimes sympathetic to, or at least very tolerant of, such communes. This difficulty notwithstanding, the “I-Thou” did save Buber from state socialism, the only practicing `communism’ that has actually achieved the status of sovereign rule in the modern world, but which yields community only by uniting workers against the self-described `workers’ state.’ Among socialists, Buber’s sober and decent view can only serve the cause of sanity, if not prudence. And among socialists, sanity must always be a cause, the object of longing, for it is surely not a given.
Recent Comments