Simone de Beauvoir: The Second Sex. H. M. Parshley translation. New York: Bantam Books, 1964 [1949].
Sonia Kruks: Simone de Beauvoir and the Politics of Ambiguity. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Although it may seem so, The Second Sex was not all Simone de Beauvoir wrote. An experienced scholar who knows her business, Sonia Kruks invites readers to see Beauvoir’s political writings as a whole. She also wants to bring Beauvoir into contemporary debates on liberal rationalism and poststructuralism, showing that Beauvoir staked out a position critical of the former without succumbing to the arbitrary nominalism of the latter As an existentialist, Beauvoir held that political judgments involve the whole being of the individual who makes them—not only the pure mind of the rationalists but that stubborn fact, the body, with its instincts, vulnerabilities, and powers. Human beings find themselves situated not only in one mind and one body (one life) but also in concrete social milieus that tend to disclose and to foreclose moral and political choices, empower and weaken the scope for political action Beauvoir thus insisted upon the ambiguity of all political judgment and action, their complex incompleteness. Oddly, and unlike her contemporary Simone Weil, Beauvoir never seems seriously to have engaged the writings of philosophers much before Immanuel Kant—precisely those who turned to political philosophy in the first place. Aristotle makes a brief appearance in The Second Sex, but only to get slapped on the wrist for having failed to understand human embryology.
Writing in the tradition of Kant, Hegel, and Heidegger—all of whom rejected nature as a source of right and defined freedom as the absence of natural constraint—the existentialists called for “active engagement in the world.” Beauvoir distinguished herself from Jean-Paul Sartre, however, by thinking more carefully about the body, “at once the site of both freedom and constraint,” and by giving greater emphasis to social relations. These concerns caused her to emphasize the ambiguity of human life, its “irresolvable antinomies,” most especially the ways in which our embodied sociality opens us both to “reciprocity” and “violent harms.” She resists all Hegelian and Marxist attempts at some grand synthesis or ‘end of History’ which would resolve these antimonies. Most interestingly, and unknowingly, she came upon something very like the Platonic and Aristotelian distinction between theoretical and practical reasoning, now approached via the existentialist notion of liberty. There is an “ontological freedom [la liberté] and the practical, or effective freedom that is required in order to act in the world [la puissance],” the latter “requir[ing] the presence and support of others.” Ignoring classical political philosophy, she soon began “to incorporate a non-reductionist Marxism within her analysis.” I am reminded of Nietzsche’s remark on Ralph Waldo Emerson: With Emerson, we lost a philosopher.”
This moral and social thinker found herself confronted with politics by 1939. But, and again understandably in view of her intellectual formation, she described this experience in historicist terms: “History seized me and never let me go again.” Very much to her credit, she continued to resist the determinist side of historicism. After the war, which she spent in occupied Paris, the French Communist Party beckoned, especially since “there appeared to be no middle ground between unqualified support for the Soviet Union and a pro-American position, which aligned one with the exploitative forces of capitalist domination and imperialism” (as distinguished, of course, from the exploitative forces of communist domination and imperialism). To her credit, she could not quite bring herself to join the party, which “demanded an unquestioning discipline from its members which Beauvoir could not accept” (that ‘freedom’ issue, again), “espous[ing] the highly deterministic, orthodox version of Marxism (or, more precisely, Marxism-Leninism) that Stalin had formulated.” With Sartre, although never merely imitating him, she would develop an existentialist form of neo-Marxism, some of which entered the thought of the American New Left a generation later. Meanwhile, and in line with a French tradition dating back at least to Chateaubriand, she toured America in 1947. In her book, America Day by Day, she displays her by now well-honed capacity for the ambiguous and indeed ambivalent response: America was “the belly of the imperialist monster,” a land of “shrill anti-Communism” and “chauvinism,” itself conflicted with its “high-flown rhetoric of freedom” and its conditions of racism and poverty; “but she is also in love with the vibrancy of America, its sheer scale, its physical and social diversity, and its lack of stuffy European formality.”
Her most influential book, The Second Sex, elaborates on the question of the relation of freedom and the body. The argument is now familiar: “Women’s material dependence on men and their lack of control over their own fertility constitute fundamental elements of their oppression,” an oppression that Marxian economics alone cannot come close to relieving. Under current social conditions, a woman lives “continuously divided against herself”: both “an active subject,” a free person, and one “who is obliged to make herself both ‘object and prey'” in the mating game. Beyond the socioeconomic ‘class’ dialectics of Marx, she insists upon an underlying sexual dialectic centered on the body. Kruks doesn’t leave it there, however, showing how Beauvoir went on to criticize French imperialism in her 1954 novel The Mandarins, subsequently bringing sexual politics, imperialism, and her ‘existentialist’ preoccupation with the ultimate limit on freedom, death, all together in her substantial memoirs, weaving the personal with the political. “Simone de Beauvoir lived her philosophical orientation to the world.”
What blocked Beauvoir from having recourse to classical philosophy was her historicist rejection of the notion of human nature, and especially the idea that the distinctive human characteristic is the capacity to reason—which, however, she identifies with Kant’s “autonomous, rational will.” “Whatever there may be that is universal to human existence does not preexist particular lives and their specific projects and is brought into being only through them.” “Projects”: There is the modernist assumption that “freedom” consists of freedom from the physical; modern materialism puts this freedom in a precarious place, in a condition (as Beauvoir would say) of ambiguity and indeed of existential threat. She accordingly rejects contemporary ‘humanism,’ including the affirmation of ‘human rights,’ denying all remnants of human nature conceived as rational in the manner of Enlightenment thinkers and the historicists who followed. Beauvoir sees, however, that to throw the ‘human rights’ baby out with the ‘humanist’ bathwater can only lead to nominalism or even nihilism, as Hitler had so forcefully demonstrated. “A critical politics does still need to be anchored in some portrayal of what it is to be human.” (To put it in the language of a later notion of ‘deconstructionism,’ if we assert ‘the death of the subject’ how can the personal be the political?) Again, Beauvoir runs up against a problem well known to the classical philosophers she ignored, the distinction between ‘human being’ as an idea and ‘human being’ as a way of life. Unlike them, she assumes that rationality cannot be the source of freedom, as indeed it cannot if rationality’s most important discovery are ‘iron laws of history.’ She settles on understanding the human being as an “embodied subject”; “the lived body [is] ‘the radiation of subjectivity.” “No exterior reality determines our choices”—as in Hegel and Marx—”yet situations that we cannot but assume may so powerfully predispose us to act in particular ways that freedom may, in practice, be significantly curtailed.” Freedom comes not from the culmination of a rationally-determined historical dialectic but in strengthened social relations “chosen, built, and sustained in the here and now”—existentially, as it were.
Aristotle finds in the reciprocal rule of husband and wife in the household the nucleus of political rule in the polis. In her own way, so does Beauvoir: As subjects, the ‘otherness’ of others “is rapidly tempered by the reciprocal realization that each one of us is an object for the other, who is thus, like us, a subject.” Unlike Aristotle, she requires that such reciprocity meet the standard of egalitarianism; in this, she registers the democratic sociopolitical regime described by Tocqueville, although unlike Tocqueville she allows it to determine her moral and political doctrine. In this sense, she is no philosopher, having never ascended from the ‘cave’ of her time and place.
In considering oppression, Beauvoir doubts that Hegel’s ‘master’ in the ‘master-slave’ struggle for recognition truly esteems his masterly status because it exacts recognition from ‘his’ slave. Upon reflecting on Beauvoir’s work, Kruks identifies three kinds of oppression: asymmetrical recognition, indifference, and aversion. Dehumanization is the most extreme form of oppression. As seen in the Nazi extermination camps—where human beings “were just so much material to be processed efficiently”—to the old-age or (as they are called) retirement homes, where “the aged are frequently viewed as nothing more than pure objects,” dehumanization means treating the subject as object, as in Hegel. But of course there is a difference between dehumanization motivated by extreme aversion, as in the ‘camps,’ and the milder aversion seen in our attitudes toward the aged, as in the ‘homes.’ Sexual politics, in distinction to both of these, derives from asymmetrical recognition; it isn’t that men don’t recognize the subjectivity of women but rather that they subordinate it by the deployment of self-satisfying myths about ‘The Woman.’ In Beauvoir’s witty formulation, The Woman is “the mirror in which the male Narcissus contemplates himself,” or, as Kruks more prosaically puts it, “the object of male fantasies.” Such ‘objectifying asymmetrical nonrecognition also describes the ways in which Europeans (mis)understand Africans, Asians, even Americans. In America itself, dehumanization manifests itself most usually in an indifference fortified by complacency in contemplating the abstract principles of the Declaration of Independence and of constitutional law.
There is a difference between the dehumanization of the aged and the other kinds. The others are remediable. Although the attitudes toward the aged taken by their relatives and caretakers may be changed, aging itself cannot. Kruks remarks that, unlike The Second Sex, Beauvoir’s late book, The Coming of Age, does not conclude with a section on liberation. To borrow a Sartrian phrase, there is no exit in this life from the coming of age. “With the approach of old age one makes the startling discovery that one’s body, in its brute physical facticity, is itself ‘Other.'” Aging kills not only our bodies but our “projects,” our freedom, along with them. The old man does nothing: “He is defined by an exis, not a praxis.” She blames capitalism for this, inasmuch as “for many, a prior life of alienated labor also means that they have no existential resources to enjoy the enforced ‘leisure’ of retirement.” Old age “exposes the failure of our entire civilization,” Beauvoir writes, hyperbolically. She does not explain why socialism, as distinguished from, say, religious convictions, could help, and Kruks has nothing much to suggest, either.
Unlike many socialists from middle- or upper-class backgrounds, Beauvoir confronted her own privilege. Drawing upon Beauvoir’s thought but also supplementing it, Kruks insists on the limitations of “a politics of self-transformation” often seen among contemporary leftists, including feminists. She blames this on “a tacit neo-Kantianism” which centers on recognition of ‘the Other’ as “an autonomous rational will.” But as Beauvoir argues, and as Kruks agrees, rationalism, however well-intentioned, won’t bring us to a condition of fully egalitarian practice. “It may be preferable to acknowledge that one is privileged but then to act from one’s privileged location: to deploy one’s privilege as effectively as possible.” Beauvoir herself began to see her own privileged position as the Algerian war of independence from France intensified in the late 1950s. In the face of French brutality in Algeria, she could not deny that she was not French. But neither did she attempt to reject “her own privileged culture, or her privileges as an intellectual” within it. “Aware of her privileged status, she instead learned to deploy it as a basis for effective, public, political intervention.” Against French nationalism vis-à-vis the Algerians, she in turn deployed an appeal to patriotism, to France as the vindicator of The Rights of Man. “In actuality, Beauvoir supported a project of decolonization that did bring very significant changes in the world (not all of them perhaps for the best).” Indeed: As Kruks observes, the Third-World ‘liberation’ movements included the 1979 Iranian revolution, itself a denial of the rights of women Beauvoir had championed for so long; she broke with such French leftists as Michel Foucault, who foolishly and unjustly supported the mullahs when they “demanded that women wear the veil.” In her own way still a child of the Enlightenment, Beauvoir didn’t like veils on anything or anyone.
Such conflicts bring Kruks back to Beauvoir’s theme of the ambiguity of politics, and of human life generally. Beauvoir rejected reason as the standard of political judgment. As “acts of situated freedom,” political judgments are and should be made “with our entire being,” including our bodies, emotions, and “personal history.” Hence she treats political judgment most thoroughly in a novel, The Mandarins, not an essay. There, the main character arrives at the same political judgment Beauvoir espoused in the late Forties: alignment with a ‘third way’ democratic-socialist party in France but geopolitical support for the Soviet Union, which, “for all its deformations,” remains “the greatest force for progress and, as such, must be given support” against capitalist, imperialist America. Such judgments must always be open to revision, however, given exactly the self-knowledge they require, and also the limitations of our knowledge, both of our situation and our selves. “A political judgment is, even at its best, but an informed and reasonable guess, one made by a particular, ‘idiosyncratic’ self in a particular situation—and like all human action it is subject to failure.” (As indeed Beauvoir’s assessment of the Soviet Union so obviously was.)
“That these personal elements play a role does not mean, however, that reason is absent,” but rather that “political judgment must be understood as an existential choice.” Although Kruks doesn’t emphasize this point, she should, inasmuch as in the absence of reason, which is really nothing more than the principle of non-contradiction, judgments and choices would descend to incoherence or, when coherent, they would be so by chance, at random.
Prudential reasoning informs political life, but its end is justice, the topic of Kruks’s final chapter. Given Beauvoir’s socialism, one expects a discussion of distributive justice, but Kruks makes the more interesting choice, turning to the question of punitive justice. In her 1946 essay, “An Eye for an Eye,” Beauvoir considers the case of French Nazi collaborator Robert Brasillach, who had publicly identified Jews and Resistance members during the Occupation, effectively guaranteeing their “deportation, torture, or execution.” An opponent of capital punishment before the war, Beauvoir admitted that her heart wanted Brasillach dead. She distinguished punishment, defined as “the purely retaliatory treatment that revenge demands,” from sanctions, “those penalties that have intended purposes other than revenge,” such as deterrence or reform. “Revenge as a response to atrocity is almost always a failure on its own terms” because it cannot erase the effects of the crime. Nonetheless, true to her contention that judgment is not and should not be wholly rational, she finds hatred of “those who commit absolute evil” and “appropriate response”—a passion but not “a capricious passion.” This especially pertains to bystanders, those not directly injured by the wrongdoer; their response expresses “the inherent sociality of individuated existence,” the “intense personal bonds” we feel for those unjustly and cruelly injured and killed. Human sociality constitutes part of “who I am.” “For our world is suffused, our existence shaped, by our participation (often unchosen) in various anonymous social collectivities.” Although Kruks herself doesn’t approve of it, Beauvoir refused to sign a petition asking for clemency for Brasillach. Brasillach deserved to suffer the death penalty, in Beauvoir’s judgment, “as an expression of society’s extreme revulsion at [his] violation” of “the values that his crimes [had] violated.” Kruks prefers our contemporary ‘truth and reconciliation’ committees, whereby societies turn to a sort of therapeutic response to atrocity. She concedes that many members of those societies find reconciliation as unsatisfying as she (and to some degree Beauvoir) find punishment and sanction. As Beauvoir concluded at the end of her essay, “failure haunts all human action, love as much as vengeance.” The persistent ambiguity of human thought, sentiment, and action did not impede her “struggle for greater freedom in the world.”
Kruks’s helpful, comprehensive view of Beauvoir’s political thought shows a thinker who, beginning and remaining entirely within the horizon of ‘late-modern’ or post-Kantian political thought, with its valorization of freedom in opposition to ‘nature’ conceived as brute matter, nonetheless can be seen as struggling with the same considerations of prudence and of justice seen in Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero. Never having studied them carefully, she ties her own thought into unnecessary knots. Given the seminal character of her best-known book, The Second Sex, her argument there should be considered in light of the handicap imposed by her own intellectual formation.
As an advocate of freedom, Beauvoir begins with critiques of the three most prominent determinisms of the time: biology, Freudian psychology, and Marxism. “The fact is that the individual, though its genotypic sex is fixed at fertilization, can be profoundly affected by the environment in which it develops.” She concurs with Hegel’s judgment that biology enables men to act as ‘subjects,’ as individuals well adapted for activity, “while the female remains wrapped up in the species.” By this she means that after copulation the male mammal is free to leave whereas the female is stuck with pregnancy. Men create; they “strike out from temporal unity in general.” Women maintain; “in the female it is the continuity of life that seeks accomplishment” in her. “The individuality of the female is opposed by the interest of the species; it is as if she were possessed by foreign forces—alienated.” This begins well before pregnancy in menstruation and continues after it in nursing the child. The woman’s individuality remains “the prey of outside forces” until another ‘outside’ force, menopause, relieves her of these natural cycles; throughout her life, “there are many times when she is “not in command” of herself. “In comparison with her the male seems infinitely favored: his sexual life is not in opposition to his existence as a person, and biologically it runs an even course, without crises and generally without mishap.” Beauvoir resolutely overlooks the satisfaction that women take in their womanhood, and especially in child-rearing.
What she does insist upon is that although these “biological facts… are one of the keys to the understanding of woman,” they do not “establish for her a fixed an inevitable destiny” and remain “insufficient for setting up a hierarchy of the sexes.” “Woman is weaker than man” (not for her the absurd claim of some later feminists, that opening up sports for girls will result in women competing on an equal basis with men on the athletic field), but her weakness “is revealed as such only in the light of the ends man proposes, the instruments he has available, and the laws he establishes”—seen particularly in violent competition. “Thus we must view the facts in of biology in the light of an ontological, economic, social, and psychological context”; “the nature of woman has been affected throughout the course of history.”
Turning then to one of those elements, psychology, she observes that “all psychoanalysts systematically reject the idea of choice and the correlated concept of value, and therein lies the intrinsic weakness of the system.” (Decades later, feminists who argued in favor of the right to abortion ‘on demand’ framed the issue in exactly Beauvoir’s existentialist terms, as a matter of free choice.) Freud, for example, “endeavored to replace the idea of value with that of authority; but he admits in Moses and Monotheism that he has no way of accounting for this authority.” In contrast, “I shall place woman in a world of values and give her behavior a dimension of liberty,” with “the power to choose between the assertion of her transcendence [of biological and other determinisms] and her alienation as object.”
The same goes for historical materialism. Contra Marx, Beauvoir contends that the aforementioned “course of history” is not destiny. Although “the theory of historical materialism has brought to light some important truths”—notably, that “humanity is not an animal species” and “human society” arises against nature, “tak[ing] over the control of nature in its own behalf” by its “practical action.” But the conquest of nature for the relief of man’s estate also relieves woman’s estate, beginning to “annul the muscular inequality of man and woman.” It also liberates women from much household drudgery (without the need to enslave other human beings) and even liberates them from multiples pregnancies and from some of the burdens of child care. Marx and Engels misunderstood gestation and childbirth as ‘labor’ in the sense of artificial production; gestation and labor, and especially the sexual impulse that leads to them, register more than “productive force” in the manner of carpentry or welding. Woman “is for man a sexual partner, a reproducer, an erotic object—an Other through whom he seeks himself.” Even under the democratic socialism Beauvoir advocates, after the abolition of social classes, “sexual differentiation would keep all its importance” (emphasis added). “Underlying all individual drama, as it underlies the economic history of mankind, there is an existentialist foundation that alone enables us to understand in its unity that particular form of being which we call human life.” For Beauvoir, for existentialism, the modern conquest of nature and the freedom it gives to the conquerors, relativizes all determinisms that modern scientists and philosophers have held up in its wake.
Indeed, history amounts to the story of this progressive conquest redounding to the favor of women. In the earliest societies nature bound women down with pregnancy and children; the true curse laid upon Eve was her exclusion from the “warlike forays” of men, “for it is not in giving life but in risking life that man is raised above the animal,” thereby “transcending” mere life by inventing tools (including weapons) and generally “shaping the future.” If this sounds very much like Hegel, Beauvoir acknowledges that indeed it does: “Certain passages in the argument employed by Hegel in defining the relation of master to slave apply much better to the relation of man to woman.” “Doomed to immanence”—the opposite of manly transcendence—for centuries, women slowly began to benefit from the victory of “Spirit” over “Life,” of “technique over magic, and reason over superstition.” Because woman instantiates the larger immanence of nature itself (more tellingly, ‘nature herself’), “the devaluation of woman represents a necessary stage in the history of humanity.” But this is only a dialectical stage, not a permanent condition, and it too shall be transcended. There are even foreshadowings of future equality in some historical moments, such as ancient Egypt, where the goddesses lived on equal footing with the gods and “woman had the same rights as man, the same powers in court,” and the same property rights. Although Beauvoir doesn’t say so, this means that the exodus of Jews from Egypt was a dialectical reversal of that early, just social condition, for which humanity as a whole was not yet prepared; in fact she will go on to excoriate Judaism and Christianity for their masculinism.
“Christian ideology has contributed no little to the oppression of women,” subordinating them under its legal code and banning abortion as a result of “endowing the embryo with a soul”; abortion thus “became a crime against the fetus itself,” which it never had been under the preceding Roman law. In “demand[ing] a new status,” today’s women “wish that in themselves, as in humanity in general, transcendence may prevail over immanence.” She avers that “it is in Soviet Russia that the feminist movement has made the most sweeping advances,” citing as evidence the constitution of the Soviet Union—not necessarily the most reliable reflection of the realities of the Soviet way of life.
As in history, so also in myths, which persist into modern times. “The cult of the leader, whether he be Napoleon, Mussolini, or Hitler, excludes all other cults.” Bizarrely (given the status afforded to Lenin, Stalin, and soon to Mao Zedong), she claims that “socialist ideologies, which assert the equality of all human beings, refuse now and for the future to permit any human category to be object or idol: in the authentically democratic society proclaimed by Marx there is no place for the Other.”
Leaving aside her pro-Communist niaseries and looking at the core of her argument, one notices that Beauvoir has a problem to solve. The earliest religions, matriarchies, valorized Woman but also identified her with nature, with immanence. Ultimately, Man must rebel against her. “It was Christianity, paradoxically, that was to proclaim, on a certain plane, the equality of man and woman” in its renunciation and indeed hatred of ‘the flesh’ along with the world and the devil. Women are equally invited to renounce the flesh, which they (in Beauvoir’s terms) live in and through. “If she agrees to deny her animality, woman—from the very fact that she is the incarnation of sin—will be also the most radiant incarnation of the triumph of the elect who have conquered sin.” However, she can only do this by worshipping and serving Jesus as the Christ—a male god. “This is the supreme masculine victory.” It can only be overturned dialectically by valorizing eroticism as the new spirituality, by a sort of Hegelian synthesis of body and spirit, immanence and transcendence, all expressed in social egalitarianism. This is possible because human life itself consists not only of the bodily but of a tension between body and spirit, necessity and freedom. “The bond that in every individual connects the physiological life and the psychic life—or better the relation existing between the contingence of an individual and the free spirit that assumes it—is the deepest enigma implied in the condition of being human, and this enigma is presented in its most disturbing form in woman.” “What is she?” For her answer Beauvoir again calls upon Egypt: Woman is “a sphinx,” the riddle, “a fundamental ambiguity” who—and that—must be addressed.
In the second half of The Second Sex Beauvoir accordingly abandons consideration of history and mythology, turning to “woman’s life today.” The modern world is the world of human transcendence, of nature-conquest. To be sure, men have led the way so far, but their victories have readied the world for the ascent of woman, that is, for full human liberation. In terms of this non-deterministic version of historicism, “One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman,” a being produced by “civilization as a whole,” a civilization that aims at such liberation by the means of conquering nature. Even in the course of nature itself, the pre-pubescent girl is physically and mentally equal to her male cohort; such feelings of inequality she may entertain result from social indoctrination, especially from bans on risk-taking—climbing trees, fighting. But with puberty, nature imposes restrictions. The girl finds herself now “consumed in waiting, more or less disguised.” “She is awaiting Man,” daydreaming of “the liberator,” the “rich and powerful” Prince Charming. To attract him, she must cultivate “grace and charm,” appearing “weak, futile, docile.” Whereas “the young man’s journey into existence is made relatively easy by the fact that there is no contradiction between his vocation as human being and as male,” the young woman becomes “divided against herself,” “doomed to insincerity and all its subterfuges.” On the other hand, this conflict, this ambivalence, causes her inner life to “develop more deeply than that of her brothers”; barred from action, she must think. Her eroticism is, because it must be, much less unsubtle than the man’s. Also, despite her natural inclination to maintain rather than to create and transcend, the woman’s life cycle manifests itself in “crises—puberty, sexual initiation, the menopause—which are much more decisive than in the male.” Natural reality stares the woman in the face more intently. Oddly, Beauvoir additionally contends that these facts makes the woman less socially conformist than men; she could only be thinking of herself, and not the generality of women, who are surely no less conformist than men.
Already, in 1949, the conquest of women has transformed marriage into a contract between “two independent persons.” Marriage for the woman is “a more advantageous career than many others,” inasmuch as most jobs are still closed to her, but it is nonetheless a career choice, not a necessity. “Today the house has lost its patriarchal splendor,” having become merely “a place to live in,” no longer the locus of ancestor-worship, as it was in ‘the ancient city’ described by Fustel de Coulanges. Middle-class women who “lack outside interests” will busy themselves with make-work projects, “just to have something to do.” (Indeed, one of the ‘moms’ in my old neighborhood would clean the house every day, topping this off by a weakly waxing of the patio tiles, and then prohibit her husband and their three sons, as well as the rest of us, from entering her spic-and-span domain without removing their shoes.) And when she does find something to do outside the home, typically her activities amount to good-works civic associational activities, undertaken again for the sake of warding off boredom—Tocquevillian civil society gone pretentious and silly. (To some extent, Beauvoir needs to denigrate women’s ‘clubs,’ given her commitment to a statist socialism that would absorb such things into its all-encompassing egalitarian embrace.)
In her drive to liberate women from what has been considered necessity, Beauvoir does not hesitate to attack the continued valorization of motherhood. Returning to abortion, she claims that laws against abortion rest on “the old Catholic argument” that “the unborn child has a soul, which is denied access to paradise if its life is interrupted without baptism.” But, she objects, the Church does not oppose capital punishment or war; indeed the Holy Wars were launched against the unbaptized. In this she ignores the obvious point that murderers and marauding anti-Christian soldiers deliberately oppose Christian principles and practices, unlike unborn children. And of course by rejecting natural right she can simply avoid the question of a natural right to life. As for the mother who gives birth, she “is almost always a discontented woman” who attempts “to compensate for all [her] frustrations through her child,” spanking her child as a means of “taking her vengeance on a man, on the world, or on herself.” It is again difficult to resist the thought that Beauvoir takes a jaundiced view toward mothers and their supposed discontentedness. She also overlooks the maternal love of one’s own, which explains the ambitions mothers entertain for their children at least as well as displaced frustration. Admitting the strength of the love of one’s own would throw both her eroticism and her socialism into serious question.
Summarizing her analysis, Beauvoir writes that “Woman does not entertain the positive belief that the truth is something other than men claim; she recognizes, rather, that there is not any fixed truth,” a recognition based on the decided changes in her own body that occur at certain junctures in her lifetime. In denying the fluidity of truth, man is the one who is finally the greater hypocrite, “pompously thunder[ing] for his code of virtue and honor” while secretly inviting woman “to disobey it” and confidently expecting her to do so. “Man gladly accepts as his authority Hegel’s idea according to which the citizen acquires his ethical dignity in transcending himself toward the universal, but as a private individual he has a right to desire and pleasure,” marrying one woman and frolicking in a whorehouse with another, or others. Under these circumstances, woman consoles herself with religion, “the mirage of some form of transcendence.”
Beauvoir assures her readers that a forthrightly atheistic if not materialist democratic socialism will change all this. Equal work, equal pay, “erotic liberty,” consensual marriage which can be broken “at will,” free contraception and abortion, State-paid pregnancy leaves, State-sponsored child care (children will not “be taken away from their parents” but “would not be abandoned to them” by society): “Only in a socialist world” can these dreams be realized. The Hegelian dialectic will be consummated in mutual recognition of man and woman, but without any permanent ‘synthesis’ or ‘end of History,’ inasmuch as “sexuality will always be materialized [in] the tension, the anguish, the joy, the frustration, and the triumph of existence.” Nature, conquered, will also be redeemed as fully human, as Marx promises. By sexualizing Hegel and Marx, Beauvoir corrects them, relieving their theories of excesses of masculine ‘transcendence’ while making socialism more humanly satisfying, less Heaven-like.
Having remained entirely within the horizon of modern philosophy, Beauvoir underestimates nature both as a physical entity and as a source of right. (It almost goes without saying that she rejects God as the ultimate source of right.) Accordingly, she assumes that she can maximize freedom and equality at the same time, a circle not so easily squared if one respects the integrity of circles and the principle of non-contradiction. In presenting laws of change as an account of Being as a whole, Hegelian logic aims at overcoming that principle, of incorporating it into a larger movement. Beauvoir’s version of Hegelian and Marxian dialectic partakes of the dubiousness of its forebears, but it has succeeded in bringing modern feminism along with it.
Recent Comments