Laurence Lampert: Strauss, Plato, Nietzsche: Philosophy and Its Poetry. Philadelphia: Paul Dry Books, 2024.
In 2015, the eminent political philosophy scholar Laurence Lampert was invited to lecture at Remain University, Beijing by Professor Liu Xiaofeng, who had read his book, Leo Strauss and Nietzsche. This “turned out to be the best intellectual experience of my life,” as Lampert found the Chinese students to be attentive, exceptionally well-versed in classical Western philosophy, and eager to engage in dialogue. For his part, Lampert carefully honed his talks in view of the needs of philosophy students living under the regime in China. His topic was the relationship between the philosophic intentions of Plato, Nietzsche, and their astute interpreter, Leo Strauss. In his first two lectures he considered Strauss’s account of Plato and Nietzsche, in the second pair he considered Plato’s account of Socrates, and in the third pair he considered Nietzsche’s account of Plato and of Plato’s Socrates.
Lampert began with Strauss’s (now familiar) rediscovery of the techniques of exoteric writing as practiced by Plato and Xenophon. In a series of letters to his friend Jacob Klein, written in 1938-39 as the twin tyrannies of ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ menaced the liberal republics of Europe, Strauss expressed his delight “at discovering what the philosophers had written as if it were just for him, which in a way it was“—just for someone like him, a Jewish thinker with family members who would soon would perish in the Holocaust, a thinker who might well be alert to techniques of literary legerdemain practiced by writers who needed to protect themselves from persecution. Strauss told Klein that he had noticed something in Moses Maimonides, no stranger to the hazards of expressing heterodox views in a political regime hostile to heterodoxy and the heterodox. Ten years earlier, Strauss had taken Maimonides as “a believing Jew,” just as Maimonides evidently wanted to be taken by the majority of his readers. Upon more careful reading, Strauss noticed that Maimonides actually regarded the world as eternal, a heterodox view indeed. Maimonides further defined Judaism as a tradition of law, with Moses as the lawgiver. “In Plato,” Lampert writes, following Strauss’s argument, “Plato the philosopher is the ideal lawgiver.” Maimonides accepts the ‘ontology’ of the philosophers along with the politics of the great political philosopher. Strauss saw that Maimonides points his readers to the heterodox core beneath the orthodox shell of his writings by leaving marks on the shell, directing his most alert, ardent, and tenacious readers to look within. The esoteric core of the exoteric teaching hides that teaching “in plain view, if you know how to look.”
In their youth, Strauss and Klein had shared a fascination with Nietzsche, a fascination not at all uncommon among young European ‘intellectuals’ before and after the First World War. Nietzsche too understood the need for exotericism, remarking three “true but deadly” doctrines that previous thinkers had often concealed: in Nietzsche’s words, these were “the sovereignty of becoming, the fluidity of all concepts, types, and kinds; and the lack of any cardinal difference between man and the animals.” These truths are deadly to political society because they are “deadly to the beliefs on which society to depends for its health.” That is, Maimonides, Plato, and Nietzsche all saw the need for philosophers to be ‘politic,’ prudent in the presentation of their teachings, the publication of which might harm the regimes under which they live and invite harm to themselves by those regimes. In the presentation of Socrates, both Plato and Xenophon hinted at, but did not fully disclose, that Socrates was “a kind of ruler and a kind of founder,” the founder of “a new kind of empire,” the “empire of a philosophic ruler” who questioned the moral conventions that prevailed in his polis, Athens, conventions upheld by the man of kalokagathia, the good and noble man, “the Greek gentleman, the pillar of civic life in the Greek civil order.” Whereas for the gentleman the virtue of moderation meant temperance tout court, including obedience to the laws of the polis, for the philosopher moderation means “controlling and guarding what you say or write”: “Philosophic moderation means in part continued use of the old moral words but understanding them in a radically different way,” a way that departs from legally sanctioned (and sanctioning) conventions. Philosophic moderation guards not an indiscriminate set of passions but a particular passion, the passion to know. “Exotericism protects society from philosophy and protects the philosopher from society.” It also provides a means by which young persons who might come to be philosophers can be tempted in both senses of the term: led by their curiosity to philosophizing, tested for their capacity to philosophize.
Perhaps even more remarkably, Strauss found exotericism in a poet, Hesiod, who, as Strauss wrote to Klein, taught that “the first things are not the gods but such things as earth, sky, stars, ocean which at one place are expressly distinguished from the gods simply.” As Lampert summarizes, “Learning what the unborn things are illuminates what the Olympians are; it shows what the gods who care about the human things are: the inventions of wise poets like Hesiod. and this enlightenment shows what wisdom is: wisdom is the knowledge of nature and human nature, and knowledge of what a god is.” Following Strauss’s hint, one of his students, Seth Benardete, would later show that “the founding poet of Greece,” Homer, was also a philosopher, indeed Greece’s “founding philosopher.” He, too, knew nature and human nature and what a god is. Strauss, Lampert remarks, “regarded the Symposium—which he called the most beautiful, thus the most poetic, of the dialogues—also as “the most important” of them “because it reveals the real secret of the [Delphic] mysteries,” the “secret truths about philosophy and the philosopher.” Maimonides learned that truth by exactly that careful reading, which requires the reader to infer conclusions that the philosopher he is studying only suggests. To understand what a philosopher thinks “you have to earn it, you have to work” at it, following his argument to its center, its core—sometimes located in the physical center of the book he has written.
In his essay on the Republic in The City and Man, Strauss makes his central paragraph a discussion of the education Socrates proposes for children in his “regime in speech,” an “education through poetry, a most important word.” The gods and heroes depicted in stories for children “teach the right kind of behavior and warn against the wrong kinds of behavior.” Socrates, Strauss writes, “lays down two laws” concerning the depiction of the gods in these stories; Lampert tells his audience that this means “Socrates is a legislator,” one who “lays down laws for the gods”—an ambiguous phrase, inasmuch as it can mean laying down laws for how poets shall depict the gods and/or laying down laws that the gods must obey. To presume to do the latter suggests that the gods are man-made, not really gods at all. This matters, because “the untrue stories the citizens [of Athens] absorbed as children are what the grown-up citizens believe: what is taken in during one’s childhood is what one continues to believe and act on as an adult”—the laws underlying the laws citizens make for themselves and their own children. This matters not only for the city generally but for Socrates’ interlocutors, which include some young Athenian gentlemen, Adeimantus among them.
Adeimantus “was beginning to experience a death of the gods,” that is, disbelief in the gods. The Homeric gods often behave badly, unjustly. If the very gods behave unjustly, why should he not do so, too? As a “decent and noble young gentleman,” Adeimantus “dearly wants to continue being decent and noble,” but “why should he take that hard and difficult way himself,” when the gods set such a bad example? Adeimantus and his brother, Glaucon entertain such doubts because they “have been brought into touch with the Greek enlightenment,” that is to say, the Greek philosophy of nature, which throws conventional opinions about the gods, opinions fostered by the poets, into question. Strauss observes that Plato’s Socrates doesn’t say what, or who, the gods are at any point in the Republic. Why not? Because Adeimantus is neither a philosopher nor a potential philosopher; he hasn’t asked ‘What is a god?’ but only ‘Why the gods aren’t more just, more moral, more trustworthy than they are.’ Socrates accordingly turns to the question, ‘What is justice?’ That is, Plato’s Socrates takes care to understand and respond to the circumstance in which he speaks, both the character of his interlocutors and the moral and political ‘atmosphere’ of the polis, Athens. “At the time of the Republic, Homer’s and Hesiod’s gods were in crisis. Socrates in the Republic sets out to be a philosophic ruler during the crisis time of Homeric religion when Homer’s gods were dying.” With his dialogues, Plato writes “philosophic poetry.” Nietzsche understood this, going so far as call Socrates “the one turning point and vortex of so-called world history”—so called, it might be added, by Hegel and his historicist followers, who may or may not be writing philosophic poetry with their claim to find reason, dialectics, in history. Chinese scholars, living in a regime animated by Marxist historicism, might be led to wonder how much of Marxism is philosophy, how much poetry.
Poēsis means making. If philosophic poetry is something philosophers make, what or who is the philosopher? And what is “the understanding of being or nature that lies behind” these poetic, theological-political efforts? And if philosophic poetry concerns the gods, the question of what a god is is a “question about being,” a question about what “the highest possible being” is. Adeimantus wants to know a principle that can guide his practice; the philosopher wants to know the answer to a theoretical question. The philosopher’s exoteric teaching is the moral, the theological-political answer; his esoteric teaching is his theoretical answer to a different question. There is a relation between the two kinds of answer because the nature of the gods has bearing on human practice, and therefore “legislating what a god is is in part an instrument in the philosopher’s rule” in Socrates, Plato, and Nietzsche. In the center of the Republic, Plato has Socrates say that unless philosophers become kings, or unless kings adequately philosophize, cities on earth will remain troubled, unjust. Socrates will never rule Athens; indeed, Athens kills him. But “Strauss shows how Socrates the philosopher actually ruled: a philosopher rules by laying down new laws for the gods; a philosopher rules by ruling the view of the gods that will rule the minds of the young men.” In the final book of the Republic, Plato has Socrates make the gods “the moral judges of human behavior” and “makes the soul immortal, living out is next life in reward and punishment for its actions in this life.” He quite literally re-forms the gods of Homer and Hesiod, reaffirming the decent, noble inclinations of the young gentlemen. Strauss calls this not only philosophic poetry but “ministerial poetry”—ministerial in the sense that it serves the regime, which has now become the regime in speech of the philosopher insofar as decent and noble young gentlemen may well become sympathetic to philosophy because kindly old Socrates, defender of decency against cynical Thrasymachus, has won their minds and hearts. Ministerial also because it is therapeutic, “giv[ing] aid and comfort to those like Adeimantus who suffer spiritually from the loss of their beliefs in justice and in the gods.” In the regime not of speech but of practice, the Athenian regime, philosophy and philosophers have not always flourished; Socrates will die at the hands of outraged citizens. Given time, the Athenian regime might have become more friendly toward such a man as Socrates, if Adeimantus and his fellow gentlemanly youths rule it.
Nietzsche famously denounced Socrates and Plato because Platonism (specifically, the theory of the ‘ideas’ or ‘forms’) made Christianity possible by preparing the minds of Europeans to accept a holy god, a god who transcends nature just as the ideas transcend the ‘cave’ that represents the conventions of the polis. Lampert considers Strauss’s presentation of Nietzsche in his second lecture to the Chinese scholars. Strauss placed his chapter, “Note on the Plan of Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil,” in the center of his book, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, following the chapter titled “Jerusalem and Athens.” “Strauss seems to be saying quietly: in the study of Platonic political philosophy, Nietzsche now occupies the central place, just after Jerusalem and Athens.” Now: after Nietzsche’s forthright challenge to Christianity and to the Platonism he claims to have spawned it. Just as the Symposium is Plato’s most beautiful dialogue, according to Strauss, so is Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche’s “most beautiful book,” a well-made example of “the exoteric art” in form, intention, and reticence. Nietzsche charges Plato with the “fundamental error” of inventing, in poetically making, the ideas—particularly the ideas of “pure mind” and “the good in itself.” In the Symposium, Socrates discloses what Delphic Diotima told him, that “human beings can only strive for wisdom or philosophize” but “gods do not philosophize” because they are wise. This is the supposed secret of Delphi that Socrates “blabbed.” On the contrary, Strauss’s Nietzsche counters. “Nietzsche divulges after the proper preparation the novelty, suspect perhaps especially among philosophers, that gods too philosophize.” As Lampert points out, in other dialogues (the Sophist and the Theaetetus) Plato suggests that the gods do philosophize, and further suggests that “the gods who philosophize are the philosophers themselves“—a blasphemous thought in any religion. If so, then Plato and Nietzsche may not be such antagonists as Nietzsche exoterically says they are. “Strauss suggests to a reader who is paying attention that Plato thought what Nietzsche thought but found it desirable to teach something different through Diotima.” Nietzsche himself ‘blabs,’ divulging “the secret about the gods philosophizing by introducing the philosophizing god Dionysos.” Qua philosopher, Socrates, Plato, and Nietzsche each knows the secret about the god, Diotima’s “noble lie about the gods that serves Plato’s political purpose for philosophy”; moreover, “Nietzsche, Strauss may also suggest, may divulge that secret “in order to serve his political purpose for philosophy.” Both Plato and Nietzsche “platonize in the service of philosophy,” having interpreted “the spiritual situation of their times” and having taught “what the times required for the well-being of philosophy.”
Strauss ends his chapter by contrasting the teachings of Plato and Nietzsche on the virtues, “one of the themes of the second main part of Nietzsche’s book,” where he attends especially to “the virtues of the philosopher of the future.” Nietzsche’s nature—aristocratic, “noble nature,” with its hierarchy of rank—”replaces nature as Plato taught it, nature and the super-natural that transcends it.” (Although Lampert says that Socratic eros is “the good in itself,” Strauss says it is “the striving for the good in itself.”) For Nietzsche, “the world is will to power and nothing else”; “will to power is Nietzsche’s name for the being of beings, the nature of nature.” Both nature as eros and nature as will to power endanger the polis. In that sense, Platonic eros and Nietzsche’s life principle, the will to power, are “deadly” truths, even if life-giving in the more comprehensive sense. Or, as Nietzsche puts it in his thirtieth aphorism, “What serves the higher type of human being as nourishment or refreshment has to be nearly poison to a very different and lesser type”: hence esotericism and exotericism. Thirty-three, the age of Jesus Christ when He died, is the number of the aphorism in which Nietzsche cautions against “devotion”—to God?—and “sacrifice for our neighbor”—that is, Christ’s Great Commandment, the sum and substance of God’s Law. Nietzsche calls such “feelings” seductions to be resisted. It is Platonism, with its City in Speech, that inclines Europeans to posit a world beyond nature, a City of God, the God Who is Logos— speech and reason. To posit, as Plato seems to do, a disembodied Mind to go along with his disembodied Ideas takes the path taken “consciously or unconsciously” by every advocate of God. Today’s philosophers ought to be more suspicious of the claim that Mind leads them to a truth, or even that the truth is more to be esteemed than appearance, an assumption Nietzsche treats as “a moral prejudice” in Aphorism 34. Life itself would not exist “if not on the basis of perspectival valuations and appearances”; a disembodied Mind contemplating a disembodied Idea would be lifeless, and he who attempted to live, so seduced, would soon perish (as Machiavelli also says of Christianity and of Platonism). Truth and neighbor-love are very far from being the same. When a Voltaire (whom Nietzsche quotes in the aphorism immediately following) says that “he only searches for the truth in order to do good,” “I bet he finds nothing!” Life is harsher than that, imposing an order of rank that puts the free minds, the undeluded ones, above the suckers. The real nihilists are those who believe in the Ideas and/or God—those nothings, according to Nietzsche.
Lampert guides his readers to look at Aphorism 36 and Aphorism 37. “Aphorism 36 is reasoning; it is philosophy. Aphorism 37 is only a kind of corollary because it follows the reasoning with something that is not reasoning but that belongs to religion.” It is an example of Nietzsche’s version of “philosophic poetry.” Lampert judges the reasoning to combine “the strictest philosophical logical seriousness and play,” presenting a “strictly logical inference about what the mind can know of the self, the other, and the world of the whole,” namely, that it is “will to power and nothing else.” He promises his audience that he “will look at the reasoning in my last Nietzsche lecture,” but there is nothing wrong with looking at it now.
Nietzsche begins with a somewhat Cartesian move, with introspection, his well-known “method.” For Descartes, introspection is the surest way to know what we can know, inasmuch as the world presented to us by our senses, thoughts, and passions may be illusory, very much including what words may be said to reveal to us about God. “Supposing nothing were ‘given’ as real besides our world of desires and passions, that we could go down or up to no other ‘reality’ than simply the reality of our drives—since thinking is only a relation of these drives to one another—: is it not permissible to make the attempt and to ask the question whether this given or something like it is not sufficient for understanding even the so-called mechanistic (or ‘material’) world?” This is more than permissible; “the conscience of method demands it.” Must we not then “recognize the will as efficient?” If so, and if (as the free spirits of the modern Enlightenment, including Voltaire himself) maintain that human beings are no different essentially from animals and the rest of nature, is not everything animated by “will force”? “The world viewed from inside, the world defined and determined according to its ‘intelligible character’—it would be ‘will to power’ and nothing else.—”
How strict is this logic, really? Is thinking “only a relation of [our] drives to one another”? In making this ‘thought-experiment,’ I incline to doubt that it is. If, for example, I think ‘2 +2 = 4’ I must have some “drive” that makes me want to think that more than anything else I might otherwise have on my mind, but the thought itself isn’t reducible to a drive or concatenation of drives. Yet that is the premise of Nietzsche’s argument. Lampert calls his argument “a comprehensive rational conclusion about the nature of nature, about what philosophy ultimately seeks,” but I think otherwise.
Lampert then turns to Aphorism 37, in which Nietzsche draws “a kind of corollary or inference” from his philosophic argument. This corollary is directed to “the free minds that Nietzsche is training,” minds that, though ‘enlightened’ in accordance the Machiavellian-Cartesian-Baconian modern project, retain the Voltairean squeamishness about abandoning the moral teachings of Christianity. “What?” they exclaim, “Does this not mean, using a popular expression: God is refuted but the devil is not—?” Nietzsche answers immediately, “On the contrary! On the contrary, my friends!” Lampert calls the addressees of this exclamation, Nietzsche’s friends, the free minds, who are experiencing “a deeply human reaction to philosophy’s rational conclusion.” Even if they are free of religion, notional deniers of God and the devil, they have yet to abandon the Christian morality in which they were imbued since childhood. But if the God of the New Testament, “the transcendent God of Christianity,” has “condemned the world as the kingdom of darkness, as the place of the devil from which he would redeem us,” and if nature is life force, will force, will to power and nothing else, then “that God, the refuted God, is the devil, the refuted devil.” Nietzsche’s will to power has a place, not for that God, but for “gods” of a different sort. “Nietzsche’s ontology introduces a new way to think about divinity, about what a god is,” and “Strauss has led his reader into the heart of this temptation“—the reference to Genesis being salient—that Nietzsche has formulated for him. More, “Strauss had suggested that Nietzsche and Plato may not differ on what a god is,” that both take “the philosophizing god Dionysos” to be the god of the philosophically-minded. This talk of divinity might confuse atheistic minds, minds ‘free’ of the belief in God, but Strauss points to passages where Nietzsche argues that human beings cannot live “without gods” of some sort; they are “necessary for a healthy social order.” Life itself justifies belief in gods, just not belief in life-denying gods. The God of the Bible does in fact give life, indeed offer eternal life, but those teachings must be false, according to Nietzsche and his “friends,” the free spirits. Real life does not transcend life as we know it on earth. Accordingly, Aphorism 57 clears the way for a new religion, “a new poetry of divinity for humans whose world can turn only around a god”—now, according to Nietzsche, the real, living god of the will to power. This is Nietzsche’s philosophic-poetic replacement for Plato’s philosophic poetry.
The exoteric doctrine, the public teaching of the new religion is the eternal return. The eternal return is “a new ideal” for human beings, just as Plato’s Ideas were a new ideal replacing the dead or dying Olympian gods. Instead of world-denying Platonism or the world-denying Christianity that, according to Nietzsche, gained traction thanks to the doctrine of Ideas, the eternal return unqualifiedly affirms life. In Strauss’s word, it is “the eternal Yes-saying to everything that was and is.” Among the Stoics, the first to give a full account of the eternal return, the cosmos undergoes periodic cycles of destruction and rebirth; for them, the moral imperative is to endure this, as a past, ongoing, and future reality, without sniveling. Christian writers denounced this as a denial of God’s promises. Nietzsche’s new religion adjures the free spirits neither to merely suffer it, nor to deny it, but to embrace it as life itself, the supreme manifestation of the will to power. As Lampert puts it, “eternal return is not a vicious circle but, on the contrary, the virtuous circle of life made eternal, made god in some sense,” “the making divine”—notice “making,” as this is an act of poēsis —of “the whole natural cycle of things,” one in which you, free spirit, will return, with the same nature and the same life experiences, as you have undergone, undergo, and will undergo in this cycle of life. “Eternal return is a non-theistic vindication of God,” an answer to what theologians call the problem of evil. It also vindicates God’s promise of eternal life. Philosophy says, “to be is the to be will to power and nothing else”; the new religion, the “political philosophy or philosophic poetry” Nietzsche makes from that insight is this “new highest ideal, the affirmation of the world as it is,” leading “to a vindication of god”—now, in the lower case—of “what alone can make a world possible for humans.” Nietzsche founds this new religion because it meets the needs of certain human beings, the free spirits, who, like the young gentlemen of Socrates’ Athens, are experiencing the ‘death’ of their own beliefs about divinity. In a sense, this parallel is a (willed) example of the eternal return.
The new religion propounds a new morality, “beyond good and evil,” as Nietzsche puts it. The “new teaching on human virtue arises out of Nietzsche’s new understanding of nature”; that is, it derives from Nietzsche’s philosophy, even if it seems to come from the new religion. “Nietzsche went beyond seeing human nature, to act on what he saw.” Human nature has been led astray by Christian de-naturing, but that isn’t the most urgent dilemma now, in Nietzsche’s time. Belief in Christianity is dying, indeed already dead in the minds of the free spirits. But Machiavelli, Descartes, Bacon and their followers have proposed the conquest of fortune and of nature by means of modern science. Modern science uses the experimental method to torture nature into revealing her secrets and then, with those secrets in hand, to invent technologies that will beat her down, conquer and master her. But, as Strauss writes, “there are no assignable limits to this conquest.” It could extend to the conquest of human nature, as “the direct result of modern virtue.” By modern virtue, Nietzsche evidently does not mean the real modern virtue, Machiavelli’s virtù, but the secularized Christian virtue of Voltaire, the attempt to remove suffering and inequality. Lampert quotes Strauss, looking at aphorisms 237 and 257: “Suffering and inequality are the prerequisites of human greatness,” including philosophy, the greatest human greatness. Aphorism 237 is an attack on what would come to be called feminism, the attempt to make men and women equal, a project Nietzsche deems contra naturam; Aphorism 257 is an attack on democracy, another form of egalitarianism. “Every enhancement so far in the type ‘human being’ was the work of an aristocratic society—and it will be this way again and again: a society that believes in a long ladder of rank order and value-difference between one person and another and in some sense requires slavery.” On this, Lampert claims, “Strauss’s point is Nietzsche’s point: the limitless conquest of nature threatens to bring about the end of philosophy.” One might add that this is exactly what Strauss says in his own voice in his exchange with the Hegelian Communist, Alexandre Kojève. [1]
Philosophers make arguments, but they also take actions. “The actions of the highest natures, the history-making philosophers,” consist of “postulat[ing] as true what they see as beneficial to philosophy and humanity in their times.” All of these postulations, all these claims, are “acts of the will to power on the part of the highest natures.” Nietzsche’s legislation, his act of the will to power, his postulation of the eternal return, “is not fundamentally a description of the way the world is, although it may be lived that way by most people”; it is really “a statement of desire, the desire of a lover” of nature who seeks to limit the conquest of nature, which “is not to be conquered through alteration but celebrated as it is.” Lampert calls this “the first comprehensive ecological philosophy.” Nietzsche is the first ‘post-modern.’
Or at least in part. “Nietzsche embraced the scientific aspects of the modern revolution while modifying or assigning limits to its technological aspects.” Modern philosophers “tamed Christianity with their philosophic poetry, their modification of Christianity’s other-worldly promises into worldly promises promising a paradise at the end of history through a scientific technology applied to nature.” This has begun to threaten human nature itself, including the highest manifestation of human nature, the philosopher. This Nietzsche seeks to prevent; evidently, the religio-poetic doctrine of the eternal return cloaks the possibility that human nature might destroyed permanently, if a philosopher does not stand up to set a limit on the conquest by calling upon free spirits to turn against the remnants of Christian morality, against the humanitarian compassion, the spirit of ressentiment that seeks revenge upon the world as it is. In becoming friends of philosophy (if hardly philosophers themselves), the free spirits will help philosophy, the activity of the highest persons on nature’s order of rank, to continue philosophizing.
What relevance has this account of Strauss have for Chinese scholars? What does Lampert’s account of Strauss’s accounts of Plato and Nietzsche bring to the Chinese? Several things, perhaps. Strauss’s account of exoteric writing and esoteric teaching would surely interest thinking men and women living in a regime in which persecution of heterodoxy is not unknown. A thoughtful Chinese might already have thought heterodox thoughts, and Plato’s critique of the gentleman, Nietzsche’s critique of the free spirits, might give encouragement to young persons among China’s ruling class to persist in thinking for themselves. If philosophers know and love nature and human nature, where does that leave Hegel, Marx, and other historicist thinkers, who suppose that nature can be triumphantly mastered? (With its air and water heavily polluted, will not an “ecological philosophy” prove healthful, live-giving?) If they do so persist, if they experience the death of the ideological ‘gods’ of their time and place, even as the young Athenian gentlemen and the modern free spirits experienced the death of gods in theirs, what gods will they put in the place of Maoist Marxism? With his account of ‘how Strauss became Strauss,’ Lampert suggests to any young potential philosopher, and to the much larger class of young free spirits, how one might become a philosopher, and how many others could become friends of philosophy, the activity of the true gods. Such persons will surely not believe that a political ruler is a true god, inasmuch as philosopher-kings rule spiritually, leaving practical politics to others. They do not believe that theory and practice can be unified, much less embodied in a human being like Stalin. Finally, there is the theme of temptation, testing by an effort at seduction. The late Professor Lampert was quite the old charmer, if his death notices are to be believed. His lectures make the claim plausible.
Note
- Leo Strauss: On Tyranny. Revised and expanded edition. Victor Gourevitch and Michael S. Roth, eds. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013. On this website, see also: “Strauss’s Critique of Hegel,” “Historicity and Reason,” and “The Philosopher-King: A Contradiction in Terms?” all under the category, “Philosophers.”
Recent Comments