Tzvetan Todorov: In Defense of the Enlightenment. Gila Walker translation. London: Atlantic Books, 2009. [First published, 2006].
Todorov asks his fellow Europeans, “After the death of God and the collapse of utopias, on what moral and intellectual base do we want to build our communal life?” No base at all, reply the postmodernists, rejecting all such ‘foundational’ thinking. Having seen postmodernism follow Church establishments and regimes animated by historical determinism into authoritarian habits, Todorov answers that Europe will more readily thrive if it recurs to “the humanist dimension of the Enlightenment.” With the Enlightenment, “for the first time in history, human beings decided to take their destiny into their own hands and to set the welfare of humanity as the ultimate goal of their acts.” Europeans can do so, again.
The Enlightenment had many dimensions. Its scientistic rationalism has attracted the most hostile scrutiny from postmodernists, but that isn’t what Todorov takes from it. He points to three principles: autonomy or free will, seen practically in the pursuit of knowledge; a telos of human benefit, as distinct from service to God or ‘state’; and universality, the acknowledgment of the human species as a whole consisting of individual rights-bearers. For the Enlighteners, that rival universalism, religion, “was the greatest target,” first and foremost as a set of sociopolitical structures claiming moral and often political authority, but second and more profoundly as theocentrism. As their name implies, humanists are anthropocentric, replacing the quest for salvation with the quest for happiness.
Humans are more readily knowable than God, and humanists worked to wrest control of the universities from the churches and their priests, who claimed to know the hardly knowable. Enlighteners also demanded an end to religious and political censorship, campaigning for freedom of thought, speech, and publication. In their publications they invented new literary genres centered on human individuals: the novel, the autobiography. Their paintings, too “turned away from the great mythological and religious subjects to show the ordinary gestures of unexceptional human beings depicted in everyday activities.” Politically, they fought for civil rights of individuals vis-à-vis the increasingly centralized modern states, along with the popular sovereignty that, they hoped, would remain vigilant in the defense of such rights. Behind civil rights, Enlighteners saw unalienable natural rights, “common to all human beings on earth.”
Natural right found its critics, however, among the Enlighteners themselves. Dedicated to the conquest of nature for the humane end of relieving man’s solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short “estate,” and buoyed by the substantial progress toward that aim by experimental modern science, many were tempted to suppose that political science might similarly conquer the unlovelier aspects of the human ‘self,’ with which Enlighteners had largely replaced the soul. They touted the possibility of human perfectibility in a very strong sense. Others—notably Rousseau—were not so tempted, and in the aftermath of the ‘totalitarian’ debacles of the past century, “we can see today that Rousseau was right.” “Knowledge of human societies comes up against the impossibility of predicting and controlling all the wills; the individual will in turn comes up against his or her inability to know the reasons for his or her own acts.” Human societies and individuals may be more knowable than God, but they are not entirely knowable, not sufficiently knowable to enable tyrants to exert the ‘total’ mastery they seek.
This self-critique of the Enlightenment can be brought to good account as Europeans seek their own identity in this century, seeking their own way of life amidst the diverse ways of life seen in the European nations. But before addressing that quest, Todorov needs to understand critiques of the Enlightenment from outside the Enlightenment. European conservatives (not to be confused with almost anyone labeled ‘conservative’ in the United States, then or now) objected precisely in the “pride of place” the Enlightenment gave “to man, freedom and equality.” Some Enlighteners, such as Montesquieu and Rousseau, agreed that their ‘project’ (itself a term redolent of the Enlightenment atmosphere) raised serious dangers. The “excessive recourse to reason,” rationalism, could not sustain the strong social and political bonds needed for an enduring political community, and any thoroughgoing doctrine of materialism would undermine individuals’ confidence in their own freedom of will along with their loyalty to civil liberty. Enlightenment could also cloak less enlightened motives, as European imperialism sought to justify itself as a vast liberation of all humanity while in fact serving “national interests.” Insofar as it did bring ideals of moral and political liberation to the conquered peoples, it inspired them to rebel against their conquerors, but often enough it was the scientistic rather than the humanistic dimension of the Enlightenment that was seized.
Nonetheless, the Enlightenment wasn’t as bad as its conservative critics alleged. It did not cause totalitarianism, as argued by T. S. Eliot, Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn, and Pope John Paul II. Or rather, the Enlightenment tout court did not—the scientistic and ‘statist’ sides of it did. “Scientism is dangerous, to be sure, but it cannot be deduced from the spirit of the Enlightenment because the Enlightenment…rejects the idea that the world is totally transparent to the eye of the scientist and that the ideal proceeds from a straightforward observation of the world,” deducing ‘ought’ from physical ‘is.’ Standing alone, without humanism, “scientism is a distortion of the Enlightenment, its enemy not its avatar.” Nor does the individualist dimension of the Enlightenment alone define it. Moral subjectivism, leading to moral relativism or to a moral doctrine of “egotistical self-love,” ignores the Enlighteners’ practice of consulting with one another, sharing the knowledge each one gained through the exercise of the intellectual and civil freedoms they prized. Montesquieu wrote that justice “is founded on the existence and sociability of reasonable beings, and not on the dispositions or particular wills of those beings.” Freedom, yes; arbitrariness, no. And that goes for sovereign peoples as well as for individuals.
Enlightenment freedom or ‘autonomy’ means both liberation from claims to rule “imposed from outside” and “construction of new norms of our own devising”—norms, that is, social customs and civil laws—not natural rights, which should guide such devising. Human beings were by nature and should everywhere be self-governing. No fools, Enlighteners “knew perfectly well that our species is not self-governing.” Individuals and groups are often “driven by their will and their desires, by their affections and their conscience, and also by forces over which they have no control.” But reason can “enlighten them in their search for truth and justice.” Political science cannot be all-knowing, but it can guide human beings to construct ruling institutions that moderate their irrational impulses and deploy those impulses at the service of effective but limited government. Within that framework, “Enlightenment thinking fosters the development of a critical spirit,” itself a check on fanatical misrule. Todorov ventures to say that “this principle still needs to be defended today, notably against those who treat to any criticism that displeases them by immediately taking the matter to court,” or at very least to the university dean or the head of the human resources department. He reminds postmodernists that “those who, benefiting from the freedom of expression that exists in the democratic public space, adopt an attitude of wholesale denigration, turn criticism into a pointless game that subverts their own starting point,” as “too much criticism kills criticism.” (That of course may be the point, however, as turning civil liberty against civil liberty is ever the tactic of aspiring tyrants in liberal democracies.)
Modern European history has opened civic space for the practice of reasonable criticism, in part by “strengthening the separation between public institutions and religious traditions,” vindicating “individual freedom” by distinguishing (as Beccaria did) between sins and crimes, offenses against God and offenses against men. Between the freedom of conscience of the ‘self’ and the legal obligations imposed by the state, with the consent of the many ‘selves’ it governs, Europe has established “a vast public or social area steeped in norms and values, which are not, however, binding”—the moeurs studied by Montesquieu and Tocqueville. This intermediate realm guards against statist usurpation of religious authority, against attempts “to found a new cult around the state itself, its institutions or its representatives.” It was, humanists admit, “the removal of the Christian Church from its dominant position” in Europe that “made this new religion possible.” As Condorcet ruefully observed, “Robespierre is a priest”—indeed, ordained by the Catholic Church—and “never be anything else,” even having switched from Catholicism to the Cult of the Supreme Being. “Alternating seduction and threats,” such a “political religion” will exercise “a tyranny that is in no way less efficient than those that preceded it,” and under “the mask of liberty,” at that. The political or civil religions of the Ancients had not posed such a threat, since in the small polis the citizen was unlikely to need defense “against his own representatives.” But political religion with the powers of the modern state behind it did pose such a threat. As Todorov remarks, in the past century, Eric Voegelin and Raymond Aron saw this as clearly as Condorcet. [2] He calls his readers’ attention particularly to the less well-known Waldemar Gurian, a Russian Jewish convert to Catholicism, who preferred not to sully the word ‘religion’ by attaching it to this phenomenon, preferring ‘ideocracy,’ which nicely conveys its ideological character, as distinguished from both religious and philosophic doctrines. “As Condorcet predicted, this new attack differed both from theocracy and from caesaropapism, inasmuch as the latter conflated the spiritual and the temporal and yet maintained the distinction between the two, requiring only that one yield to the other whereas the new political religions eliminated the distinction and sacralized either the political power itself, in the form of the state, the people, or the party, or the regime that it imposed, namely, fascism, Nazism or Communism.” Totalitarian ideologies “replace and supersede religion.” Europeans must never submit to them, again.
Todorov analyzes the idea of freedom as “autonomy” by distinguishing two kinds of acts and discourses it entails. “The aim of one is to promote good; the other aspires to establish truth.” The Enlighteners separated morality from science “in order to remove the knowledge of man and the world from the control of religion.” Considering education, for example, Condorcet recommended “national education,” which consisted of promoting moral and political principles, from “public instruction,” teaching empirical facts and mathematical calculation. Readers now will recognize Weber’s famous distinction between facts and values, here. Condorcet warns that government has no “right to decide where truth resides or where error is to be found” or “to decide what is to be taught in school,” in terms of scientific and mathematical instruction. “Truth is above the laws.” Republican government is the realm of deliberation, not scientific investigation. As with Weber, Condorcet demands that legislative powers, “contingent upon popular will alone” remain separate from “regulatory powers,” wielded by administrators, who do have recourse to science. Todorov follows this, even to the point of opposing natural law teachings in the moral and political realm, finding them too scientistic. But he drops off when it comes to granting authority to scientific administrators. “The temptation to rely on ‘experts’ to formulate moral norms or political objectives, as if the definition of what is good proceeds from knowledge,” leading to the attempt “to absorb the knowledge of human beings into the knowledge of nature and to ground moral and political conduct in the laws of physics and biology” should lead Europeans to reject the authority of bureaucrats. “There are other paths to knowledge than science, as Giambattista Vico insisted, even at the height of the Enlightenment. [3]
This means that “scientism and moralism are both alien to the spirit of the Enlightenment,” despite what one often hears. “Truth cannot dictate the good but neither should it be subjugated to it.” Worse still are the later attempts by totalitarian and even democratically elected rulers, at times taken up by religionists and postmodernists alike, to erase “the very distinction between truth and falsehood, between truth and fiction,” to serve moral or political ends. Todorov cites the teaching of ‘creation science’ in schools and what he takes to be the deliberately false allegation of the existence of weapons of mass destruction in Saddam Hussein’s Iraq as examples of this, but he surely knows of the attempts to suppress free speech in the universities, as well. The abuse of Enlightenment principles threatens individual and political freedom, wherever it is practiced.
“Autonomy alone cannot suffice to characterize the Enlightenment’s ideal conception of human conduct,” however. Free will is all very well, “but to go where?” Since “all desires and all acts are not equally worthy,” and since the Enlightenment rejected the Bible as a source of moral standards, Enlighteners turned to “humanity itself” as its standard: “Whatever contributes to the welfare of human beings was deemed good,” as human happiness on earth replaced the salvation of souls in Heaven. [4] In contemporary Europe, now that the totalitarian deformation of Enlightenment principles has gone so catastrophically wrong, “people have stopped pinning their hopes of worldly happiness and self-fulfillment on political structures at all,” making the state into “a mere service provider.” This ‘privatization’ of the pursuit of happiness ignores the moral and political importance of civic engagement. Todorov continues to resist the lessons conservatives draw, rejecting the Enlightenment’s “Copernican revolution” of morals and concluding, with Dostoevsky’s character, that if God is dead, everything is permissible.” Freedom has rightful limits.
The principal limit to individual freedom is “the fact”—and notice it is a fact, not a ‘value’—that “all human beings belong to the same species and that consequently they have the same right to dignity.” That is, Todorov does not go all the way with Weber. Acknowledging the natural ‘species-being’ of man, he thinks of it not so much as the source of natural right—being nervous about deriving ‘ought’ from ‘is’—but, more vaguely, from “universality.” He would meet Hume’s challenge with Kant’s reply, initially by way of Rousseau. The acknowledgment of universality leads one away from immorality, defined as selfishness, insofar as (per Rousseau) “love of the human race” brings us to consider the general interest. “It was in this spirit,” the spirit of equality, purged of its naturalism, “that Kant was to formulate his categorical imperative.” Other Enlighteners formulated the theory espoused by “the modern school of natural law,” which Todorov ascribes to both the American “Declaration of Rights [sic] in 1776 and the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen in France in 1789.” Unlike either the Americans or the French, Todorov derives a prohibition of capital punishment from these rights.
Because, unlike the natural rights theorists, Todorov prefers to sever morality from nature, he needs to find a counter to the fanaticism of the dogmatic assertion of ‘human rights.’ “If human rights are the sole unquestionable reference point in the public arena and the unique yardstick by which the orthodoxy of discourse and acts is judged, then we find ourselves in an arena of political correctness and media lynching, the democratic version of a witch-hunt—a sort of one-upmanship of virtue, the effect of which is to eliminate the expression of thoughts that diverge from it. This moral blackmail lurking in the background of all debates is harmful to democratic life.” To counter this, he recurs to the doctrine of consent, the limitations set by contracts and other legally recognizable forms. Although this criticism cuts into the pretensions of postmodernists, given his interest in Europe as a whole, he chooses rather to emphasize international law deriving from the Peace of Westphalia—particular the principle of non-intervention into the internal affairs of sovereign states without their consent. That is, he doubts the morality of ‘humanitarian intervention,’ just as he had set himself firmly against European colonization. “A noble end cannot be achieved by ignoble means”—and he clearly regards killing in war an ignoble means—because “the end will be lost on the way.” Europeans should “draw a clear line between proposing and imposing, influencing and forcing, peace and war; the first term does not negate our compassion for the suffering of other; the second does.” Plurality, yes, so long as “it avoids radical relativism”; universality, yes, so long as it does not override consent.
Although the humanist element of the Enlightenment has universal validity, it originated in Europe. Why there? Elements of it can be seen in other places, other civilizations, but not the Enlightenment tout court. Todorov credits Europe’s “political autonomy,” freedom of sovereign states and of individuals. “Europe is at once one and many,” its states constituting “a kind of system…connected by commerce and politics,” underpinned “by the same general principles.” Ancient natural law traditions, along with Christianity, unified Europeans on the moral and political side, “the unity of science,” perhaps deriving from ancient philosophy, unified them on the ‘knowledge’ side. “At the same time, Europeans were equally aware of the differences between their countries and, above all, the number of those countries. “One cannot help being struck by the contrast in comparison with China, for instance, which covers about the same area: a single state on the one hand as against forty-odd independent states on the other.” (Indeed, it wasn’t so long ago when Germans alone populated thirty-seven such states.) Hume saw the significance of this: China is eminently civilized; “it might naturally be expected to ripen into something more perfect and finished, than what has yet arisen from them.” But, Hume continues, China’s advancement in science and morals has been retarded by its homogeneity—one language, one system of laws, one set of moeurs. Without contrasts to consider, without competition (except between warlords on the peripheries of the empire and the imperial center), “minds were dulled by the uncontested reign of authority, traditions and established reputations.” Although often at each other’s throats, Europeans enjoyed “the advantages of diversity,” including ” cautious attitude towards established assertions and reputations.” In this, Europe resembled ancient Greece, with its many small city-states and its contending philosophic schools. And contemporary European states have republican regimes, frameworks for plurality within unity. Todorov again recurs to Rousseau: the “will of all” is the sum of individual wills, expressed in practice by majority rule, which can incline to majority tyranny. But the “general will” limits the will of all by holding no citizen to be “inferior to others” but entitled to “equality before the law.” The general will seeks “a generality that encompasses differences.” Sidestepping Rousseau’s firm adherence to natural right, and rejecting the imposition of unity by force, Todorov would “encourage people to recognize that their perspective is partial, to detach themselves from it (to act ‘in the silence of passions,’ to borrow Diderot’s expression), and to position themselves from the standpoint of the general interest,” an act that “requires seeing thing from the point of view of our neighbor, whose opinion differs from our own.” This, he trusts, would integrate individual differences “into a superior form of unity,” first by encouraging tolerance, fostering a critical spirit, and facilitating detachment from ‘one’s own.’
But is this not a tepid brew? It may be “a certain European spirit that the inhabitants of the continent can be proud of,” and it is European in its origin, and many other places today share the Enlightenment heritage, precisely because Europeans conquered and colonized so much of the world. However, “This common substratum does not suffice to organize a viable political entity” in Europe itself. As Charles de Gaulle once said, “Good luck to this federation without a federator!” And de Gaulle, who famously identified himself with France, also recognized that “Sartre, too, is France.” That is, both the world at large, with its modern but anti-humanist regimes, and Europe itself, with its latter-day Sartres, poses a threat to the humanist decency Todorov upholds. As Todorov himself recognizes, “Faith is a European tradition but so is atheism, the defense of hierarchy and that of equality, continuity and change, the expansion of the empire and the fight against imperialism, revolution as well as reform and conservatism.” These facts notwithstanding, “the ability to integrate differences without erasing them distinguishes Europe from the world’s other great political areas: from India and from China, from Russia and from the United States.” Unlike the United States, for example, Europe “not only recognizes the rights of individuals, but also those of historic, cultural and political communities that are the member states of the union.” True, but if that is a strength, why can’t European defend themselves without the assistance of the (somewhat) more coherent American Union? At least so far.
Military and political defense of the Continent of the Enlightenment will continue to be needed. “The traditional adversaries of the Enlightenment—obscurantism, arbitrary authority and fanaticism—are like the heads of the Hyra that keep growing back as they are cut,” drawing “their strength from characteristics of human beings and societies that are as ineradicable as the desire for autonomy and dialogue,” such things as security, comfort, groupishness, and the will to power. And so “the vocation of our species,” and not only of Europeans, will be “to pick up the task of enlightenment with each new day.”
Notes
- For a full discussion, see Todorov, The Imperfect Garden: The Legacy of Humanism. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002. For a discussion of this book, see “In Defense of Humanism,” on this website under the category of “Nations.”
- For a review of Voeglin’s Hitler and the Germans, see “Voegelin, Hitler, and the Germans” on this website under the category of “Nations.” For discussions of Aron, see Raymond Aron: Aron et De Gaulle and Liberté et Égalité on this website under “Aron and De Gaulle: Wartime and Postwar” on this website under the category of “Nations” and José Colen and Elisabeth Dutarte-Michaut, eds. The Companion to Raymond Aron on this website under “Aron Companion,” also under the category of “Nations.”
- See Giambattista Vico: Principles of the New Science of Giambattista Vico Concerning the Common Nature of Nations. For discussion, see “What Is Vico Trying to Accomplish?” “Vico’s Periods of History,” and “Seeking Wisdom in Poetry,” on this website under the category of “Philosophers.”
- See, for example, François-Jean de Chastellux: De la Félicité Publique, ou Considérations sur le sort des hommes dans les différente époques de l’histoire (1772).
Recent Comments