Amy Gutmann: Identity in Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003.
‘Identity politics’ has its partisans. Citizens in democratic republics often organize around “ethnicity, race, nationality, culture, religion, gender, sexual orientation, class, disability, age, ideology, and other social markers,” forming “identity groups” intended to exert political influence on such regimes. Gutmann wants to understand what this means for democracy—whether such organizations are good or bad when it comes to securing “democratic justice.”
Identity groups arise whenever a regime respects individuals’ “freedom of association”; indeed, “a society that prevents identity groups from forming is a tyranny.” Many modern tyrannies have attempted to eradicate identity groups altogether, earning the pejorative title, ‘totalitarian.’ Gutmann defines democracy as a regime animated by three principles: civic equality, liberty, and opportunity. Civic equality means “the obligation of democracies to treat all individuals as equal agents in democratic politics and support the conditions that are necessary for their equal treatment as citizens.” Equal freedom means “the obligation of a democratic government to respect the liberty of all individuals to live their own lives as they see fit consistent with the equal liberty of others.” Basic opportunity means “the capacity of individuals to live a decent life with a fair chance to choose among their preferred ways of life.” In terms of democratic justice, then, identity groups “are not the ultimate source of value in any democracy committed to equal regard for individuals,” but neither are they necessarily a source of evil. “Equal regard for individuals—not identity groups—is fundamental to democratic justice.” Identity groups that regard themselves as the ultimate source of value might easily “subordinate the civil equality and equal freedom of persons (inside or outside the group) to their cause” by, among other things, denying individuals the right “to live their lives as they see fit.”
Nonetheless, identity groups may have value in democracies. If the moral principles esteemed by the group comport with individual freedom, the group will strengthen members’ commitment to that. Also, “numbers count in democratic politics,” so individual members of identity groups will exercise more influence within the regime than they could if they acted alone. In organizing themselves this way, citizens can better secure their civic equality, their freedoms, and their opportunities. Finally, “even when identity groups do not combat injustice, as long as they do not inflict it, they can be valued and valuable for the mutually supportive relationships that they provide their members.”
Identity groups may be organized or unorganized, inside or outside government institutions, based on a chosen (e.g., an ideology) or unchosen (race) characteristic. Identity groups are not the same as interest groups. An interest group “organizes around a shared instrumental interest”; its members may not ‘identify with’ one another for any other reason. The interests they pursue precede the formation of the group; members aggregate to secure something they want. Identity group politics centers on “a sense of who people are.” Though distinct, interests and identity usually find themselves in “close connection.” “Democratic politics is bound up with both how people identify themselves and what they therefore want”; group identities and interests often reinforce one another, as seen in the civil rights movement of the 1960s.
Although the civil rights movement sought reforms consistent with democratic justice, their enemies in the Ku Klux Klan, equally an identity group, did not. As the example shows, identity groups may or may not “impede democratic justice.” “When mutual identification entails putting considerations of group identity above considerations of justice…identity group politics is morally suspect.” This has often been the case—so much so, that critics of identity politics charge that it endangers democracy itself by discouraging compromise, encouraging sectarianism, and making too much of characteristics not chosen but imposed by accidents of birth. On the other side, partisans of multicultural politics often present themselves as “preoccupied with supporting particularistic identities and interests,” ignoring or denying “egalitarian principles” central to democracy.
Gutmann tellingly cites James Madison on faction. Madison defines a faction as any group that opposes the public good—an interest group or, for that matter, identity group which practices and preaches injustice. In the tenth Federalist, Madison famously insists that since factions are to liberty what fire is to air, it is futile to destroy liberty in an attempt to stamp out injustice. For Gutmann, who defines identity groups not as necessarily factitious but as neither good nor bad as such, “identity politics is an important manifestation” of the liberty Madison defends. And the regime of democratic republicanism deserves defense. It is not a neutral political instrument but a way of “institutionaliz[ing] in politics a more ethical treatment of individuals than the alternatives to democracy, which range from benevolent to malevolent autocracies and oligarchies.” Therefore, “identity groups need to be assessed by the same standards that one would apply to any groups that make political claims and exert political influence in democracies.”
In her case, these standards inhere not in natural rights of individuals but in civic equality. “There is no ethically neutral place to evaluate the contribution of identity groups to democratic societies, nor would a neutral place be desirable if it were available.” Rather, the regime of democracy “can and ideally should be a deliberative democracy, offering opportunities for its citizens to deliberate about the content of democratic justice and to defend their best understanding of justice at any given time.” This, she seems to believe, makes it unnecessary to conceive of rights as natural, although they might not be historical in the ‘ontological,’ Hegelian and Marxist sense of a rationally ascertainable and predictable course of events that determines the best understanding of justice at any given time. That is, she emphasizes the deliberative or prudential dimension of reasoning, not its theoretical or (putatively) scientific dimension. She may not consider nature as anything but ethically neutral, and thus an unfit source of moral principles.
Far from being a historical determinist, Gutmann considers a “just democracy” a regime that “respects the ethical agency of individuals”; “since individuals are the ultimate source of ethical value, respect for their ethical agency is a basic good.” Such agency has two components: “the capacity to live one’s own life as one sees fit consistent with respecting equal freedom for others,” and “the capacity to contribute to the justice of one’s society and one’s world.” Political ethics in a democratic regime consists of “a public commitment to treating individuals as ethical agents,” neither as “atomistic individuals” with no social or political obligations to one another nor as cells in a larger organism, with no capacity to deliberate and to choose. Civic equality, equal freedom, and basic opportunities serve as “preconditions of a fair democratic process” but also stand as “valuable in their own right as expressions of the freedom and equality of individual persons as ethical agents.”
For this reason, Gutmann cautions against thinking that all identities are group identities in a morally or politically relevant sense. My personality surely ranks as part of my identity, but I don’t organize a group based upon it. “Wise or foolish, careful or careless, neat or sloppy, serious or light-hearted,” I am unlikely to reach out to my fellows to organize politically on such bases. On one occasion, a frustrated assistant of President Charles de Gaulle slammed down the receiver of a telephone, shouting, “Death to all fools!” De Gaulle happened to be walking by and intoned, “Ah, Monsieur, what a vast project you propose.” Surely too vast even for the Gaullist politics of grandeur.
Gutmann devotes one chapter to each of what she considers the four main identity groups: cultural, associational, ascriptive, and religious. A cultural identity group “represents a way of life that is (close to) ‘encompassing’ or ‘comprehensive'”; in Aristotelian terms, it is a regime with the sovereignty subtracted. As such, one’s culture forms a part of ‘who a person is.’ When any person engages in democratic politics, he therefore brings his culture with him, often making claims on his fellow citizens on behalf of that culture. And the group he belongs to which organizes itself around the shared culture will give those claims more political heft. Since “democratic politics typically depends on some dominant culture that includes a common language (or languages), school curricula, occupations, ceremonies and holidays, and even architectural styles, that are not culturally neutral,” a minority culture will pursue ways to defend itself, especially if the dominant culture “is alien and therefore alienating to them.” Members will demand “equal freedom and respect” from members of the dominant culture. Yet no large, modern democratic regime can fully accommodate all claims of all the minority cultures within its territory, since democracies need citizens who can speak with one another in order “to act coherently” and to maintain political union. This begs the question, “What kind of political claims on behalf of cultural identity groups are justified in democracies, and why?”
Gutmann agrees with cultural identitarians when they assert that cultures provide “publicly important goods” to a democratic regime. “Every person needs a context of choice”; a culture or way of life provides such a context, although it also narrows it by defining the range of choices consistent with that way. The question for democrats then becomes, how narrow is that range of choice? And does a given culture “offer equal freedom to its members”? That is, “the state and the dominant public culture that it supports, both indirectly and directly, cannot be culturally neutral.” What claims made by organized cultural minorities can it accept and what claims must it reject?
As a democrat and a feminist, Gutmann respects many of the claims made by the Pueblo tribe in defense of its cultural practices. But one of those practices denies civic equality to women. A United States District Court sided with the Pueblo tribal council against Pueblo women who brought a lawsuit against the council under the U. S. Voting Rights Act and the equal protection clause of the United States Constitution. The Court ruled that “to abrogate tribal decisions, particularly in the delicate area of membership, for whatever ‘good’ reasons, is to destroy cultural identity under the guise of saving it.” Gutmann judges this “a particularly suspect argument in the context of a case brought by women to claim their civic equality as Pueblo.” The Court granted absolute sovereignty to a cultural group which denies a fundamental principle of the democratic regime which should exercise sovereignty over it in the name of that principle. “Respect for culture cannot mean deference to whatever the established authorities of that culture deem right,” although there may be prudential reasons for leaving well enough alone if “trying to resist injustice would likely be futile or counterproductive.” In the not-so-distant past, some Amerindians engaged in slavery, cannibalism, and torture; had these practices persisted into the late twentieth century, the minds of our august justices might have seen what they were arguing more clearly and, one hopes, argued differently.
“Legitimate political sovereignty needs to rest somewhere.” That being so, “what degree of sovereignty should any group be granted, and by what standards may its sovereignty be limited…out of respect for individual rights?” Gutmann answers that sovereignty seldom is, and never should be, absolute. “A cultural perspective goes awry at the start if it rests on the premise that a single culture encompasses the identity of the individuals who are its members,” as if cultures were “homogeneous wholes.” As a matter of fact, some members of every culture will “imagine beyond it” even as they use the “resources” of that culture to do so. Just as a minority culture may rightly oppose a democratic majority that makes “oppressive claims” upon it, so a democratic majority may rightly oppose a minority culture that oppresses its members, recognizing them as “fellow persons who can reciprocally recognize the basic freedom and civic equality of all persons, regardless of their gender, ethnicity, and nationality.”
“If there is a right to culture, on democratic grounds, it must be an individual right to shape one’s own identity, partly through cultural affiliations.” There is no “fundamental moral standing to a group qua group” because “once we treat a cultural group as having fundamental moral standing, we are logically led to subordinate the claims of individuals to the morally fundamental group.” Indeed, “the right to oppose cultural practices that violate basic rights is as fundamental any right within a democracy.” If Gutmann were a natural-rights liberal, this distinction would be easy to make, but because she is not, she needs to base her liberalism what might be termed cross-culturalism.
Against Judith Butler, who accuses human rights advocates as “unjustifiably privileging a particular culture—the culture of human rights—over all others,” denying that any “external standards by which to judge any culture” exist, except “the standards of another culture,” Gutmann replies that “critics of oppressive cultural practices need not claim to stand above other cultures.” Rather, in upholding human rights, democrats in fact “stand inside cultures,” but they “stand inside many cultures.” There are democrats in ‘the West’ but there are also democrats in ‘the East,’ democrats in the United States, China, Russia, Iran, Brazil, Germany, Zaire, and partisans of autocracy and of oligarchy in all those places, as well. This is because the “rights culture” isn’t really a culture at all. It has no common language or literature, no common visual art or music, no distinguishable way of dressing, celebrating, or mourning. “Human rights doctrine is multicultural,” and “so is its rejection,” whether by Chinese or Russian today, Japanese or German yesterday.
“Democratic standards are shared by particular cultures that can defend human rights in their own way.” There likely will be occasions when these differing ways seem to contradict one another in ways that also contradict those standards. In these instances, “democratic deliberation across cultures about the content of human rights is one way of furthering our understanding.”
Gutmann next moves to the claims of “associational” identity groups, the kind Tocqueville esteemed as checks on majority tyranny. Membership in these is entirely voluntary. It is good for a number of reasons, among them being that they promote a political way of life, that is, a life animated by “reciprocity,” including “mutual aid.” Care must be taken to ensure that such groups do not violate “the conditions of equal freedom of association” by excluding those who wish to join them “out of prejudice.”
Gutmann affirms Tocqueville’s claim that voluntary associations have value in democratic regimes. They do indeed support liberty—specifically, the liberty of persons to “identify themselves as they themselves see fit rather than as government—or any other powerful agent in society—determines for them.” They “are an antidote to atomistic individualism that is completely consistent with a free society.”
Even groups which “reject democratic values” may be tolerated in a democracy so long as they do not inflict injustice on other persons or groups. You are free to join the International Monarchist Society (if there is one), so long as you don’t oppress anyone who is either a member or a non-member of it. A criterion for judging whether an association has overstepped this limit is whether or not a member can “exit it and still live a decent life.” Leaving the United Auto Workers imposes more hardship than leaving the American Fern Society.
Gutmann seeks a mean between the extreme of removing the freedom of association altogether by “forcing all associations to include anyone who wants to join” and the extreme of “permit[ting] all voluntary associations to exclude would-be members on any grounds.” The UAW should be entitled to discipline any member who takes bribes from an auto manufacturer in order to induce him to take a weaker position when bargaining over a contract; it should not be entitled to exclude someone from membership on the basis of race, class, gender or any other characteristic irrelevant to the democratically legitimate purposes of the organization. “Democratically legitimate purposes” are those which do not obstruct “civic equality.”
Gutmann considers two Supreme Court cases centered on policies of voluntary groups. In Roberts v. United States Jaycees (1984), the plaintiff challenged the Jaycees’ denial of membership to women on the grounds of nondiscrimination. An association of businessmen, the Jaycees provide what she describes as a “public good,” namely “professional contacts.” Businesswomen were being denied the opportunity to ‘network’ on equal terms with businessmen. It is of course questionable whether the opportunity to do business deals in a social setting is a public good at all. It looks rather like a private good, a setting for one-on-one transactions. Be that as it may, Gutman sets down three “features of discriminatory exclusion [that] create a strong case for public intervention”: that “the exclusion must be discriminatory based on false or statistical stereotyping”—in this case, that women somehow have no interest or ability to engage in commerce; that “the discriminatory exclusion occurs in a public realm and is connected to the distribution of a public good”; and that “the voluntary association is not primarily defined by its dedication to an expressive purpose,” by which she means the expression of opinions, the restriction of which would violate the First Amendment. On the most dubious point, Gutmann claims that, according to “their own stated purposes,” the Jaycees aimed at providing and promoting the skills of “solicitation and management” as public goods, presumably meaning that they were serving the public good by those aims. If so, would it have made a difference if the Jaycees had simply claimed to promote the business interests of their members, with no rhetoric about serving the public good at all? In other words, as Gutmann rightly asks, “How broadly should we construe the realm of public goods and services?”
In Boy Scouts of America v. Dale (2000), the plaintiff objected to the Boy Scouts’ exclusion of openly homosexual boys and men from their organization. The Court upheld the Boy Scouts’ right to do so, but Gutmann argues that while homosexual behavior might be a criterion for exclusion, homosexual identity should not be. Until (for example) a homosexual man does something “that justifies denying [him his] equal freedom or civic equality,” such as committing sodomy with underage boys, he should not be barred from membership. She acknowledges a complication. “What makes the Boy Scouts case both difficult and troubling is that free identity expression is centrally at stake on both sides,” necessitating some rational “ranking” of “the competing values of free expressive association”—the Boy Scouts uphold the principle of being “morally straight”—and “freedom from discrimination.” Gutmann’s preferred solution here is to permit the Boy Scouts to continue their policy but to deny them any government support, as for example the use of public-school buildings for their meetings. Generally, “the more freedom that expressive associations have to discriminate, the less state support they should receive beyond the support of legal toleration.” She does not consider the possibility that lawsuits of this sort are intended to advance the claim that homosexuality and homosexual activity are morally straight, that the plaintiffs intend precisely to override “free expressive association,” just as she stands ready to override it in the case of the Jaycees.
She concludes her discussion on voluntary associations by citing “an underappreciated fact.” Between 1960 and 1990, membership in such associations declined. At the same time, Americans were “becoming more tolerant by all available measures,” in their opinions and in their actions. She doesn’t seem much to mind the trade-off, although it may evidence the increased bureaucratization of American life, threatening the liberty she esteems. See Tocqueville on the perils of democratic despotism.
Things get more interesting when Gutmann turns to considering “ascriptive” identity. “What distinguishes ascriptive identity groups is that they organize around characteristics that are largely beyond people’s ability to choose, such as race, gender, physical handicap, ethnicity, sexual orientation, age, and nationality.” Every one of those categories is natural or has roots in nature. One can make choices in relation to them, but only to the extent of deciding whether to join or leave an organization centered on them in some way. One can base that choice on whether or not a particular organization is “justice-friendly.”
Ascriptive identity groups closely resemble interest groups because ascriptive identity and material interests intermingle in “dynamic interaction.” After all, “people’s interests and understanding of their interests are as identity-driven as their identities are interest-driven”; “ascriptive identities inform peoples interests.” “Even in the extreme case of someone who adopts an ascriptive identity that he had never before seriously considered as his group identity in order to make a living”—at the risk of unkindness, one may think of Barack Obama—the “identity plays a causally important and independent role in shaping how the living is pursued.”
Given the intimate bond between ascriptive identity and self-interest, ascriptive identity groups can still be justice-friendly if they “encourage subordinated individuals to organize and stand up for themselves,” admit members of other ascriptive groups into their organization, and form coalitions with other groups in pursuit of “the general cause of democratic justice.” During the civil rights movement of the 1950s and 1960s, that is of course exactly what the NAACP and other organizations did, with substantial effect. More, “there is no good reason why obligations to fight injustice should be placed first and foremost at the feet of members of disadvantaged groups.” Other justice-friendly groups should seek to join them.
By contrast, when ascriptive groups are “least successful, they create new (or deeper) divisions among the disadvantaged and convey the dangerous impression that people need only band together on the basis of their ascriptive identities and not on the basis of their common humanity or a commitment to fighting injustice whoever its victims happen to be.” The virulent response of the recent Black Lives Matter operatives to the slogan “All Lives Matter” may be taken as a case in point, and an unsurprising one, given BLM’s origins in neo-Marxism.
Just or unjust, to what extent do ascriptive identity organizations really represent the groups they claim to represent? For example, how many American women endorse the policies propounded by the National Organization of Women? Obviously, no such organization can represent the opinions of all those mentioned in its grand title. Therefore, it should “recognize a burden of representation to those individuals who are associated involuntarily with the group” by scrupulous “avoidance of injustice.” The temptation to treat members of out-groups roughly should be resisted; the temptation to deal roughly with members of their own group who do not fully concur with the organization’s principles and policies should be resisted even more. Closely related to this danger is the tendency to urge group members to “take pride” in their identity. “What sense does it make to take pride in an involuntary identity?” None whatsoever: If justice requires that I not be blamed for an identity I didn’t choose, then I cannot claim credit for it, either. Rather, “the appropriate object of pride is not the ascriptive identity in itself but rather the identity’s manifestation of dignified, self-respecting personhood, the personhood of someone who has overcome social obstacles because of an ascriptive identity.”
Given the fact that injustice “is a moral blight on democracy, and therefore on everyone’s life within it”— one “especially great on the lives of people who materially benefit from injustice but do nothing to combat it”— there is a more comprehensive form of identification than those favored by particularistic identitarians. Individuals are in fact “bound up with living in a more just society,” and should recognize “that contributing without undue sacrifice to making society more just will improve their own lives.” Without acknowledging it, quite possibly without knowing it, Gutmann here makes exactly the same kind of argument George Washington liked to make: Your interests and the interests of your country very often cohere with your moral duties. As she puts it, “our interests are bound up with our identification with other people, and our identification with other people makes us want to contribute to making our society more just.”
However her relations with America’s first president may stand, Gutmann leaves no doubt that she knows the Golden Rule: “We can perceive it to be in our own interest to contribute to fighting injustice insofar as we identify with other people, and therefore with a society that treats other people justly, as we wish to be treated ourselves.” This takes her to the interesting point I alluded to: “Humanity itself is an ascriptive identity, identification with which can serve the cause of justice.” Human beings form a natural species, to which all capable of reading her book belong. Since “democratic justice cannot leave anyone out of its reach,” it requires “identification with humanity and a commitment to justice.” Very well then. Humanity is natural. Justice is right. Put them together, and they spell out ‘natural right.’ For all her ‘deontological,’ Rawlsian gesturing, an attempt to drive out nature with a pitchfork, Gutmann finds herself brought to witness nature’s return.
Following reason, she devotes the final main chapter to revelation. Natural-right political philosophy solves the religio-political problem by permitting any religious practice that doesn’t violate natural rights. A congregation of pious Aztecs are welcome, provided that they refrain from sacrificing virgin girls to the Sun God, a ceremony violative of the natural right to life. In terms of U. S. constitutional law, this has meant free exercise of religion combined with separation of church and state, which Gutmann calls “two-way protection” of human rights.
Her primary interest is in defining and protecting the right to conscience. This is because no more personal, no more individual aspect of religion exists. Further, conscience exists in the souls of religious and non-religious persons alike, forming a commonality (based, again, on human nature) between citizens who otherwise might find little in common. Further still, my conscience likely differs from yours, which means that if we are to live together as fellow citizens, we need to address that fact. Gutmann resolves this latter difficulty by appealing to politics as Aristotle defines it, as “reciprocity.” As an observer of democracy in the Greece of his time, Aristotle didn’t much associate reciprocity, ruling and being ruled, with that regime because in his experience the many who were poor inclined to seek unjust rule over the few who were rich. Gutmann’s modern-liberal understanding of democracy enables her to think of it more along the lines of what Aristotle calls a mixed regime, which does indeed engage in political or reciprocal rule.
“Rather than deny the truth of revelation for political purposes, democrats” of Gutmann’s persuasion “argue that revelation by itself cannot justify a coercive law because it cannot reasonably expect the public assent of citizens who have not experienced it and do not share the religious faith of those who take its dictates on faith.” What democrats can do is to acknowledge those religious truths which “can be defended by publicly accessible arguments,” suitable for democratic deliberation. “Then it is the argumentative force of a revelation, judged in nonrevelatory terms, that is doing the justificatory work for democratic purposes, not the revelation itself.” This is essentially where natural right puts the matter.
Given the fact that natural right no longer finds wide acceptance of modern liberal democracies, and especially not in universities, Gutmann appeals once again to Rawls, who “recommends the democratic ideal” because it lacks a “necessary foundation in any comprehensive philosophy” but instead overlaps “with all reasonable philosophies, where reasonable philosophies include religious ones.” Because it appeals to reason, this “ideal”—which Rawls arrives at with ‘deontological’ legerdemain—rules out fanaticism religious and secular, ‘Islamist’ and Leninist alike. “Reasonable moral faith” can be held by “religious or secular persons, so long as they are democrats”—a clever reworking of Kant’s famous sentence in his Perpetual Peace, “the problem of setting up a state can be solved even by a nation of devils, so long as they possess understanding.” True, faith “goes beyond reason, but reasonable faith is compatible with what the best methods of reasoning can deliver at any time.” And it is compatible with reciprocity, which “does not require agreement among citizens or arguments on the same secular or religious terms.”
Why Rawls, instead of Aristotle ‘all the way down,’ as the saying goes? It seems that Gutmann inclines to the Humean claim that you can’t derive the moral ‘ought’ from the natural ‘is.’ “A purely empiricist position would yield no commitment to democratic justice or to treating people as civic equals, since evidence and log alone are morally inconclusive”; “empiricism is amoral” and empiricism is the way of modern natural science. Whether empiricism suffices to understand human beings insofar as they are natural beings is a question Hume takes to have been settled.
In practical terms, Guttmann (following Rawls) doesn’t care so much whether a democracy respects “ethical personhood” as seen in conscience because conscience is taken to originate in God or nature or reason or “human individuality itself,” so long as the regime understands that such respect is indispensable to its existence. “Conscience and democracy share a fundamental premise: persons are ethical subjects.”
That being so, how shall democracies deal with the fact that ethical subjects often conscientiously disagree with one another? How can democracy justly resolve the rational contradictions that arise from the free exercise of conscience? Guttman answers that whereas “respect for conscience is a moral good because it reflects respect for the ethical identity of persons, a respect that democratic governments cannot consistently reject,” such respect “cannot be an absolute value for democratic governments because it can conflict with other basic democratic principles such as equal liberty.” The fact that one conscience may call for war and another call for peace proves that “conscience is ethically fallible.” And so is “democratic decision-making,” which generates laws and policies individuals may conscientiously endorse or oppose. Once again, there needs to be politics, reciprocity, deliberation—mutual testing of arguments and counterarguments in the public square.
“The great challenge to democratic governments is to decide when conscientious objection should be accommodated, even though the law in question is legitimate.” One answer to the challenge would be to say ‘Never.’ Such an accommodation would smooth the slippery slope toward anarchy. The opposite answer would be ‘Always,’ or at least whenever the objector doesn’t reject “a basic democratic principle” such as civic equality or equal freedom.
The first answer would track a strict separation of ‘church’ and ‘state.’ As Locke recommended, a conscientious objector should be free to defy the law so long as he accepts the punishment established for that defiance. Gutmann considers this too harsh. “A stable democratic state can and should exempt conscientious citizens from some legitimate law and in so doing resect their conscientious objection,” and therefore their ‘personhood,’ “without harming other innocent people.” If strict separationists worry that some will fake conscientiousness in order to evade the law—a common enough occurrence during the Vietnam War—then the regime can establish boards of review requiring of the objector some plausible proof of his conscientiousness, such as “past actions and affiliations” indicating “that they hold a set of conscientious beliefs that can qualify them for the status of conscientious objector.” While “not a foolproof test”—the review board is attempting to ascertain the inner character of another human being”—it is fair enough for government work.
The second answer, maximizing “accommodation of conscience” by the regime, would fail to “reciprocally protect other citizens of the state from the harms that can come from conscience.” Why should my conscientious objection to a war, or to war generally, result in your conscription? Those who would maximize a government’s accommodation of conscience “are reluctant to recognize is that a democratic government”—even a democratic government—cannot do that “without undermining the legitimate purposes of democratic government”—its need to defend the country against foreign attack or civil disorder, its need to collect revenues, and the like. They “do not expect conscientious citizens to support democracy supports them, by abiding by laws that are legitimate and democratically elected.”
To avoid the tyranny of democracy over individuals, or the tyranny of individuals over democracy, one needs not a Berlin Wall of separation of church and state, or not wall of separation at all, but “a permeable wall of separation” whereby conscience and democracy limit one another. Gutmann’s democracy will “accommodate conscientious dissenters when doing so does not discriminate against other conscientious dissenters or undermine the legitimate purpose of the law,” thereby publicly acknowledging “the centrality of ethical commitments to the identity of persons, and the contribution that those commitments can make to democracy.” Such “reciprocity is the lifeblood of democratic justice.”
In conclusion, Gutmann remarks, “without ethical precepts to guide group identity, members of groups are blind and can just as easily tyrannize over others as aid them. When guided by ethical precepts, individuals can enlist group identity as a justifiable means for organizing in democratic politics.” Her emphasis on the classical understanding of regimes and of politics as ruling and being ruled in turn raises her treatment of ‘identity politics’ well above most of the other available accounts written in the past couple of decades.
Recent Comments