Elzbieta Matynia, ed.: The Uncanny Era: Conversations between Vacláv Havel and Adam Michnik. Translated by Elzbieta Matynia. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2014.
Prophets and philosophers alike often doubt or deny that truth may be found in political life. The truth shall set you free, Jesus teaches, but attention to ‘this world’ will enslave you, block you from finding God. Socrates discharged his civic duties without enthusiasm, devoting his life to private conversations in which he dismissed even the great Pericles as a mere builder of walls.
Yet the Kingdom of God Christians seek is, after all, a kingdom, a regime. The God of the Bible chooses a particular people, establishing not one but several regimes for it, adjusting His political strategy to his people’s changing circumstances, and eventually exiling most of them to the Babylonian monarchy when he runs out of patience with their uncivil behavior. Universalizing Jesus denies the distinction between Jew and Greek, but nonetheless calls out His people for membership in His assembly or church—founding a regime, if not one ‘of this world.’ As for Socrates, he initiates not philosophy but political, dialogic philosophy, engaging citizens and foreigners in dialectic while eschewing the practice of previous philosophers, who had sought to behold the truths of nature directly, without regard to the opinions that prevailed in the polis.
From time to time, the late Vacláv Havel—Czech playwright, sometime dissident, eventual president of the Czech Republic—joined longtime friend and fellow dissident, Polish essayist and sometime politician Adam Michnik to discuss these and related matters. Both men preferred the Socratic direction. Havel had participated in the Prague Spring of 1968, when the political underground of dissidents in Czechoslovakia surfaced in street demonstrations against the Communist regime, installed two decades earlier by the Soviet Union. The Red Army rolled in and suppressed the uprising. In her informative introduction to this volume, New School for Social Research Graduate Faculty member Elzbieta Matynia (no stranger to political activism in her native Poland) recounts that Czech and Polish dissidents held a secret meeting in the mountains along the border of the two countries in August 1978, a decade after their early hopes for freedom had been disappointed. Havel and Michnik met at that time.
Their hopes had been disappointed, but not killed. At the meeting, they “plott[ed] democracy in both countries,” and not, as it transpired, in vain; eleven years later, in 1989, the Soviet empire collapsed and many of these same dissidents themselves took positions of authority as founders of the new, republican regimes of Central Europe. Revolution came first to Poland, where, “the principle of a nonviolent, self-limiting revolution, guided by an unrelenting commitment to create alternative institutions outside the state’s control, [had] led to the first solid promise of democratic change” in the states dominated by Moscow since the Second World War. When Michnik and several other newly-elected Polish parliamentarians visited Havel in the summer of 1989, Michnik told the incredulous Czech, “Before year’s end you’ll be President” of Czechoslovakia. And so, astonishingly, it was; not for nothing does Matynia consider the era “uncanny,” taking the term from Michnik’s own title for a published conversation with Havel held in Prague in 1991. But the term “uncanny” refers not to the peaceful overthrow of the old regimes—in Czechoslovakia, they called it the “Velvet Revolution”—but to the end of ‘post-communism,’ the end of the aftermath of those revolutions. Revolutions clarify; post-revolutionary conditions see the return of complexity, ambiguity.
As it happens, Americans are (or should be) quite familiar with many of the questions raised in this and the subsequent conversations recorded here. After the American Civil War, a victorious United States government attempted to ‘reconstruct’ republican regime in the states of the defeated Confederacy. Slaveholding plantation oligarchs had established their rule over the Southern states decades before the war; in firing on U. S. forces at Fort Sumter, South Carolina, they had asserted the independence of what had been an anti-republican (and therefore unconstitutional) regimes for a long time. Now that they had been defeated, what would become of these oligarchs? How would these states be returned to the American Union in conformity with the United States Constitution? The results of Reconstruction were to be mixed, as many ‘old South’ grandees re-established themselves, re-subordinating if not re-enslaving their former slaves. How would Czechoslovakia and Poland fare, as they attempted to consolidate regime changes of their own? We have six conversations between Michnik and Havel, from the years 1991 to 2007, followed by two pieces published by Michnik after his friend’s death.
Michnik opened the 1991 conversation by asking if there might be a restoration of the Communist ‘old regimes’ in Central and Eastern Europe. Havel considered this “out of the question.” He did, however, accurately predict the rise of former Communists “return[ing] under a slightly repainted banner,” namely nationalism. But the Soviet Union as an empire won’t return. The problems now were the huge state-owned enterprises and state bureaucracies, complemented by “the habits of normal average citizens” who “got accustomed to the fact that the omnipotent state towers over them,” like a father who doesn’t want his children to grow up. This has indeed proven to be a real problem, and not only in post-communist countries.
Michnik identified two approaches to consolidating regime change, one seen in Poland, the other in Czechoslovakia. Polish republicans drew “a thick line between the past and the present,” saying that “the only criterion for judging bureaucrats would be their competence and their loyalty to the new order.” Czech and Slovak politicians preferred the policy of lustration, a term derived from the Christian idea of penitence followed by purification. Havel advocated an in-between ground leaning toward lustration; penitence and purification, yes, but followed by forgiveness on the part of the victims of the former regime for those who served in that regime. There were gradations of guilt, ranging from genuinely evil characters to those who were forced to collaborate by the regime, and even some whose role in the underground organizations was precisely to collaborate, in order to gain access to information or to inflect regime policies in a liberalizing direction. “The boundary can be designated only by something intangible or something that does not lend itself to legal norms, such as feelings, taste, understanding, prudence, wisdom”—what Aristotle would immediately recognize as natural right. In his own case, “Shortly after I became president, I was given a list of all colleagues who had informed on me, but that same day I not only lost the piece of paper but on top of that I forgot who was on the list.” But that was on the personal level. “As president I have to take into account that society needs this kind of accountability, because they have a sense that the revolution has not been completed”; those who “terrorized the population and in obvious ways abused human rights” must be removed from office.
Ever the secularist, Michnik remarked that although the Catholic Church has a firm understanding of sin, forgiveness, and absolution, it also organized the Inquisition. Havel replied that “absolution is always connected with confession,” acknowledging sin, “whereas the Inquisition is about tracking down the hidden sins.” Michnik concurred, concluding as Havel had done that “we can absolve only those wrongs done to us, but to absolve the wrongs suffered by others is not in our power.” He worried that revolutionary revanchism may never end, as indeed it did not, in France, until the despot Napoleon redirected French hatreds outward, to the destruction of large swaths of Europe. Havel acknowledged that the pent-up hatreds were real, because Communism had the opposite effect its practitioners intended. Instead of accelerating ‘History’ or the course of events toward a benign and wondrous culmination, Communist regimes actually “postponed [history’s] natural development and movement,” interrupting what, by the early twentieth century, had looked like a gradual democratization of civil societies accompanied by republican regimes. “Here in Czechoslovakia, in every little town or county, one can see that people are reaching back for traditions were destroyed over forty years ago”—that is, in the 1930s, initially by the Nazi invasion. Long suppressed, both good “spirits” and bad “demons” are now “awakening,” the demons being both religious and ethnic hatreds, anti-Semitism among them. If such demons prevail, the political result will be not a return to communism but a return to fascism, which in the Czech region was secular, but in the Slovak region allied with elements of the Catholic Church. This ties in with the problem of democracy: “Democratic rule, when compared with the prior totalitarian rule, inevitably appears indecisive, uncertain, insufficiently strong or energetic,” a “feeling [which] constitutes fertile ground for those who yearn for rule with an iron hand” by “the so-called strong personality.” This notwithstanding, Havel rejected Michnik’s worry that “anti-Communism” by itself inclines toward fascism. “I think that if nothing intervenes in this normal development, then in time the political spectrum will stabilize” because “concrete political work will begin” under the new republican regimes. And Michnik himself, after all, remained a critic of Communism: Under such regimes, “It was enough to know a few formulas to be wiser than Plato, Heidegger, or Descartes.”
What will replace the Communist ideology? “Ideas,” Havel replied, by which he means a kind of post-modernist globalism—’post-modern’ in its rejection of the grand thought-systems produced by the likes of Hegel and Marx (exactly the sort of system easily vulgarized into the “few formulas” criticized by Michnik), globalist in a sense that he does not immediately make clear, but which seems to involve both a sense of international law fortified by international institutions along with the variation of natural right seen in environmentalism. Michnik challenged Havel on this point. “Is the era of ideology really ending? Isn’t that just wishful thinking, the yearning of humanists and intellectuals?” His concerns about the rise of nationalism were more intense than Havel’s. Havel conceded that national sentiments will remain strong, if only because they do not require mastery of even the most elementary philosophic doctrines: “Everybody knows his nationality.” Xenophobia arises from closed societies where people do not speak with one another, do not learn to live together, and from the desire to assign guilt for whatever troubles confront us. Xenophobia thus has both a ‘regime’ basis and a natural basis. “I think a lot of time must pass before civil society will respect all the dimensions of our ‘self’ will appreciate the matter of national belonging but not encourage a sense of superiority, and will not turn it into an ideology or the organizing principle of the state.” In this, perhaps without not knowing it, Havel took the stance of that Frenchman of the previous generation, Charles de Gaulle.
Michnik wanted to know what Havel thought of “the role of religion,” now that the Communist regimes are gone. “Under the Communist dictatorship it was for all of us a source of strength, whether we were religious or not. It was our only recourse to a natural law that we all had to answer to.” What now? Havel found in religion “two dimensions,” one indispensable to good politics, the other dangerous to it. Religion “puts things into perspective, as it directs human attention upward, reminding us of the metaphysical anchoring of our conscience and our responsibility, because it emphasizes brotherly love and unselfishness.” But it also may enter political life more directly—this “might be stronger in Poland than here”—and remains lethally strong in Muslim countries. A regime founded upon “seemingly” religious but actually “ideological and doctrinal principles” becomes “in its essence intolerant, because it reduces the human being to one dimension of his life, constrains him and manipulates him,” just as such secularist ideologies as communism and nationalism do. Havel suggested that “after the collapse of Communism religious or nationalist fundamentalism may come to the fore,” but the “force that acts against them, a force that I hope will succeed,” is “the power of the survival instinct of this planet.” In other writings, Havel refers to this as the “Gaia hypothesis”—that the earth itself, including the human beings living on it, has a sort of organic wisdom, which rebalances itself when some portion of it runs to any extreme. For example, he cited the international military response to Saddam Hussein’s invasion of Kuwait, “which could be interpreted as a sign of those survival mechanisms.” So yes, fundamentalism endangers us, but it “fac[es] forces that are capable of withstanding it.” But those forces are not simply mechanistic or automatic; they will require statesmanship to “quickly strengthen democratic institutions, mechanisms, and the rules of the game. Democracy has to earn its authority quickly,” or it will have authority rested from it by ‘authoritarians.’
Such institutions will include a stronger executive branch of the Czechoslovak government (not popular election of the president, but veto power and the right to dissolve the legislature and call for early elections), an institution which can serve as “the most effective weapon against those who come in with the idea of rule by an iron hand” by imparting decisiveness to a regime in which the legislature, the ‘talkative’ branch, currently enjoys too much power. Political discussion, to be sure, but also political decision must be a hallmark of republicanism, lest more forceful ‘deciders’ persuade the people, unaccustomed to the republican way of politics, that republicanism itself must go. On the other side (and glancing at his own political rival, Vacláv Klaus), while a free-market economy underlies lasting prosperity, Havel denied that “the market mechanism is a magical key that will solve everything, nor do I think that the free market is a worldview or the meaning of life,” a conviction familiar to Americans who read Ayn Rand. Libertarianism makes such a sensible institution as private property and the law of supply and demand which follows from it into yet another ideology aiming at yet another utopia. The law of supply and demand should rather be understood “as something that has been tested for centuries,” something that “resonates with human nature, and functions in a natural way.” “This is not a religion.”
Havel and Michnik next met four years later, also in Prague. By 1995, Havel was no longer president of Czechoslovakia because there was no longer a Czechoslovakia; he had resigned in protest when Slovaks declared their independence in 1992. Promptly elected president of the new Czech Republic, he recalled that “with the collapse of Communism the structure of habits, values, and ways of life also collapsed”; “people had to organize their lives anew,” not fully understanding that they would need to do this, that it wouldn’t be done for them by rulers ‘from above.’ In democratic republics, “those who come to power will only be of a kind that the society is capable of generating,” and post-communist societies had suffered serious deformations. He marvels at the success of the American Revolution, attributing it to a situation in which people did not win “over others but rather that principles won.” (He was half-right: Principles did win, but the Tories left for Canada and their property was expropriated.) Principles or no principles, human nature remains the same, regardless of the regime, and human nature is a mixed bag. Given the experience in ruling large organizations and their extensive interpersonal networks built during their years in power, ex-Communist officials enjoyed political and economic advantages, leading to “some kind of Velvet Restoration,” in the years after the Velvet Revolution.
Unlike Czechoslovakia, Michnik observed, Poland entertained few such starry-eyed hopes. “Our revolution was a revolution without a utopia”; “we had no illusions like those of the Jacobins or Bolsheviks.” Accordingly, his concerns focus not on internal faction but on international military alliance. He awaited Polish accession to NATO, impatiently. Havel, with experience foreign policy, explained that the delay had occurred because “contemporary politicians are much more constrained” by mass-media pressures than the framers of NATO were. What is more, “Today there are no politicians as courageous and magnanimous as Adenauer, de Gaulle, and Gasperi after the war.” He worried that Americans especially tend to assume that now the revolutions have been accomplished, all will be well. But not so. Russia remains both insecure and ambitious, located as it is on the eastern part of the Great European Plain. Eastern and Central European countries will need protection from Russian irredentism, even if the full reconstitution of the Soviet empire under the new regime in Moscow remains improbable.
Meanwhile, and disturbingly, nationalist and religious factions had boiled up in the Balkans, in the form of exercises in ‘ethnic cleansing.’ The Kosovo War “can only be stopped by outside force,” but for the moment “there is no political will” to exert it because “Western politicians are not prepared to make quick decisions,” often lacking firm executive authority in their regimes but also, even with such authority, constrained by media scrutiny. “If the new European order is not created by democrats, nationalists will take care of it.” But if Czech and Polish democratic republicans can “notice the dangers lurking in the contemporary world and to articulate them in the right way thanks to the specific experience of Communism and our entire history,” this may spur West European and North American politicians take action. For Havel, this is what ‘thinking globally’ means: the defense of commercial republicanism against a new, ‘authoritarian’ nationalism, fueled by revenues from state-owned enterprises and fired by an ideology of ethnic triumphalism and domination. Medium- and small-sized countries like Poland and the Czech Republic can in this way take the lead in world affairs, even without the material resources of the major powers. In the event, the Czech Republic did support NATO’s intervention in the Balkans, the following year.
By November 1998, the time of their third conversation, Havel had been re-elected president. He was still “not worried about Russia” as a genuinely imperialist force in Europe. He now worried more about what he called “a fundamental issue for the future of our civilization,” challenged by politicians and intellectuals in Asia who argued that “democracy is a great thing but it has to stop somewhere, because democracy without limitations leads to a crisis of authority and sooner or later brings about chaos.” Havel wasn’t concerned about anarchy, but he did contend (as André Malraux had done, thirty years earlier) that “if our civilization does not somehow deepen spiritually, if it doesn’t realize anew its own spiritual roots, if it doesn’t start to respect moral principles, we are threatened with a disintegration of our human bonds, the loss of a sense of responsibility, and totally unbridled self-interest.” “To some extent, I’m a product of the sixties”—a product, that is, of a “decade of cultural, spiritual and social rebellion against all establishments.” True enough: unlike Malraux and de Gaulle, however, it’s hard to tell if he sees that the rebellions of the ‘Sixties lacked precisely the “spiritual roots” he saw missing from the West of the uncanny era.
In 2003, when they next met, this time in Poland, Havel had left office (his rival Klaus succeeded him) and was recovering from cancer. He continued to discuss the “crisis of civilization,” a crisis “deeper than the crisis of democracy.” He set himself resolutely against historical determinism. “I believe that all people are agents of historical events, except that there are many people, and they are different, and so history depends on lots of factors.” The overall trajectory of technological mastery over nature has yielded “a huge variety of benefits that make daily life easier” while it also threatens the environment and (with the prospect of modern weapons in the hands of terrorist gangs) “coexistence on this planet.” Such a civilizational contradiction stems from the contradictions of human nature itself; “a human being remains a creature full of contradictions, as he always was.” We are not only the first planetary civilization but “the first atheist civilization.” By what light can such a civilization illuminate its path?
Michnik replied, “You are on the same wavelength as John Paul II,” and “I don’t agree with this.” Atheism, no; secularism, yes. The West still has principles, an orientation towards ‘Being,’ even if they remain unstated or poorly stated. Further, religion isn’t enough; Muslim terrorists are religious. “As long as civilization exists, the need for metaphysics will endure.” For example, “nobody reasonable will accept the thesis that it’s a matter of moral indifference that there is a regime in Iraq which chops people’s hands off, plucks their eyes out, cuts off their ears, and the world is to look at that quietly in the name of the holy rule of sovereignty.” Neither he, nor Havel, nor the Pope partook of pacifism in such matters, even if they preferred velvet revolutions to violent ones. Havel didn’t dispute Michnik’s correction, except for one important caveat: “The state is the work of people, while the person is a work of God. There is some hierarchy here.” His metaphysics has religious dimension, albeit one consonant with the natural rights of individual persons. The media-driven, publicity-hound politics which prevents the formation of outstanding statesmen, reducing politics to “public relations” and thereby establishing a “cult of mediocrity” becomes possible when human beings keep their eyes on what is around and beneath them, and never on what, or who, is above them. The youth of the ‘Sixties has seen the crisis of civilization more clearly now, precisely because he has engaged in politics. In that sense, a man can indeed seek and find truth in political life.
Their next conversation occurred in October 2007, the year Havel published his memoir, To the Castle and Back. Havel asked Michnik about the political circumstances in Poland, where the Kaczynski brothers had been elected on a nationalist platform. Michnik said that a coalition of three right-wing parties had been “changing the system” in Poland “in a stealthy, creeping way”—attempting a revolution of the velvet glove, as it were, a garment that leaves no fingerprints behind. What he called the Polish “Fourth Republic,” with its “permanent ‘moral revolution'” backed by the security services and the Polish equivalent of the attorney-general’s office, used wiretaps and denunciations by informers to enforce a never-ending purge of regime ‘enemies,’ especially of anyone who could be accused of having had ties to the Communist regime. Prime Minister Jaroslaw Kacynski had been “able to persuade many people that Poland is ruled by a secret pact that ought to be tracked down and destroyed”—that is, he made use of a populist conspiracy theory to aggrandize his power. “The real model is the consistent and effective authoritarianism of Vladimir Putin” in Russia. “We should look at the practices of Putin to understand the nature of the threats to democracy in the countries of post-Communist Europe,” which amounts to a sort of Slavic Francoism. All this notwithstanding, Michnik remained guardedly optimistic. “Poland is a country where no nastiness ever wins out in the end. In Poland, everything is possible: even change for the better.”
The following year, Havel had returned to his first love, the theater, writing several plays before his death in 2011. They met in the offices of Michnik’s newspaper in Warsaw, the city in which Havel chose to stage the premiere of his first new play in many years. Recalling the Soviet invasion ending the Prague Spring of 1968, Havel recalled that the attack “opened the eyes of the Western left” to the character of the Soviet regime, an awakening that seemed to occur about once every decade or so, and needed to, given the somnolence of the Left when it came to threats from that quarter. Michnik and Havel worried that some former dissidents in Russia, Solzhenitsyn by far the most important, might now be the ones who have fallen asleep, when it comes to the depredations of Putin and other rightists. Havel remarked, “In Russian society there lurks a peculiar complex, an anxiety as to whether it will be taken seriously in the West. This, the biggest country in the world, appears to itself to be small, and that is why it glances at neighboring states as though it doesn’t know exactly where Russia begins and where it ends.” This anxiety has given us Dostoevsky and Tolstoy, but also Stalin and Brezhnev and Putin—not to be confused, to be sure, when it comes to the amount of blood on their hands, but not to be trusted, either, when it comes to the independence of Eastern and Central Europe. “There are no totalitarian pressures any more, that doesn’t mean we have won.”
Shortly before Havel’s death, Michnik published “When Socrates Became Pericles,” an article marking his seventy-fifth birthday. Michnik recalls how Havel would bring drinks to the secret police agents who were freezing outside the door of his house on winter nights—a characteristic gesture of compassion and good-humored irony. “Theater of the absurd is Havel’s specialty.” But far more than a mere sense of the absurd: “I was struck by how he evaded all attempts at simplistic classification: he was not a mutinous Communist… nor was he a Catholic. He was neither a conservative nor a liberal, nor was he a Social Democrat…. Simply put, he was a democrat, a shy, gentle, and modest man with great courage, imagination, and determination.” He understood that it’s not enough to ‘stand on principle’ because most people can’t afford to do that; they need a way to survive. Michnik finds “as good an illustration as could be found of the historical legacy with which Havel wrestled throughout his life” in a 1938 essay by the novelist and playwright Karel Capek. At the time it seemed as if those living under Nazism could choose among “shared culpability, cowardice, or martyrdom.” “But there is a fourth way,” Capek wrote: “Refusal to betray one’s spiritual discipline, no matter how difficult the circumstances and no matter what pressures, refusal to deny the spirit of independence and conscious awareness,” a spirit which tells us “that reason can be universal, and experience, cognition, laws of the spirit, and laws of conscience can still have binding power.” The question of how to win the Cold War, how to secure a decent regime in its aftermath, had been preceded long before by the question, “How to lose?” In an open letter to Alexander Dubcek, who had wanted “Socialism with a Human Face,” Havel had warned that the Communists’ “desire to bring you to your knees will not be satisfied simply because you no longer have power; they need more; they need you to lose face.” The only thing that can be salvaged, for now, is self-respect. This was no situation in which political calculation would serve. Like Lincoln in 1861, de Gaulle in 1940, “the sudden assertion of human criteria within a dehumanizing framework of political manipulation can be like a flash of lightning illuminating a dark landscape.” Dubcek wasn’t up to such an assertion. Havel was.
In a letter to Dubcek’s Soviet-installed replacement, Gustáv Husák, Havel predicted the eventual collapse of the Soviet empire and of the Communist regime in Czechoslovakia. He was right, but also came to think that the modern project itself, especially the “technological society” it has produced, eventually would suffer collapse, as well, for the same reason: its denial of the human person. You can drive out nature with a pitchfork, the ancient Greek poet wrote, but she will return. That is, Havel concurred with Heidegger regarding technology and the conquest of nature it is intended to effect, but refused to follow Heidegger into radical historicism, much less suffering illusions about the “inner truth and greatness” of Nazism. Closer to his Czech home, he is following the lead of Capek, who wrote extensively on the challenges technology poses to the human person, and indeed popularized the word ‘robot’ in a play first staged in 1920. For Capek and Havel alike, nature, not ‘History,’ will have the last word.
It was this intention to assert “human criteria” that guided Havel in his decision to remain in Czechoslovakia and go to prison instead of fleeing to the United States. The simple fact that by 1979 the regime preferred not to kill him but to offer him a choice between incarceration and exile proved that the regime itself was beginning to hesitate, by then, to question its ideology. By going to prison he could put his principles into practice, proving himself to his friends, to God, and to himself. As Michnik writes, the “dissident subculture had snares of its own”—”demonizing the enemy” and “angeliz[ing] oneself.” But for Havel, “the enemy was the Communist system, not the Communists”; a Christian would call that hating the sin, not the sinner.
On the matter of religion, too, Michnik provides a just assessment of his friend, who “rejected the atheist worldview”—possibly in part because it is a worldview, a too-confident system of ‘totalizing’ belief. Havel was rather a “philosophically inclined homo religiosus” who delivered himself of the extraordinary sentence, “I accept the Gospel of Jesus as a challenge to go my own way.” That doesn’t sound quite like what Jesus had in mind, but it does indeed bring Socrates to church. This “outlook” (not “worldview”) inflected his politics, Havel’s considerations on Machiavelli’s modern ‘state.’ Michnik quotes him as identifying the origin of lo stato to “a moment when human reason begins to ‘liberate’ itself from the human being as such, from his personal experience, personal conscience, and personal responsibility and so also from that to which, within the framework of the natural world, all responsibility is uniquely related his absolute horizon.” Understanding that ‘Machiavellian moment’ in Western thought enabled him to “unmask Marxism-Leninism as a para-religion offering ready-made answers to all questions”; against this, he (“in his own way”) upheld “a religion that demands humility in the face of Mystery.” Politically, such humility issued in a commitment to “political and economic pluralism, along with dialogue between democratic representatives and expert opinion”—the two components of modern republican government.
The choice for Havel, then, was between attempts to take an idea (or more usually a closed system of ideas) and institutionalize it and the attempt to live in the world of politics Socratically, “living in the truth.” Michnik observes that Havel never claimed to have coined that phrase, although it came to be identified with him. It was Jan Patocka, “an intellectual mentor and moral authority for the Czech dissidents,” who did so, associating it with Socrates and pointing out that Socrates eventually was put to death by the regime of his city. Havel “chose, like Socrates, uncompromising conflict with the authorities. And astoundingly, by happenstance, this time Socrates became Pericles.” And although his vocation ended less grimly than Socrates’, his move to abolish the death penalty (and, it might be added, to pardon most of the old-regime operatives) brought unwelcome grumblings from a less-than-Socratic public stuck in a “Czech small-mindedness” that Michnik perhaps too quickly associates with “petty bourgeois provincialism” instead of with democracy itself. There weren’t many bourgeois in Socrates’ Athens, and no Czechs at all, but there were plenty of democrats. In this, Michnik relies too much on the formulas of the nineteenth-century European ‘Left,’ insufficiently on Tocqueville.
The continued rise of rightist populism in Europe and elsewhere shows that concerns of Michnik and Havel were far from groundless. Some of the appeal of these groups may arise from hyper-nationalist sentiment, but one must also notice that it responds to the persistent moral flaccidity of many contemporary democratic republics, and also to the longstanding political problems raised by bureaucracy—especially by international and ‘globalist’ bureaucracy, which hardly deserves the name of either democracy or republicanism. Solzhenitsyn had pointed to the moral crisis of the West as early as 1978, in his much-misunderstood commencement speech at Harvard University. This must explain, at least in part, his late-life sympathy for Putin. Among European thinkers now, Pierre Manent may best articulate an answer to these concerns, and to these groups themselves, but how many are listening?
Recent Comments