Eyeing death, Montaigne negotiates with his reader over the terms of his immortality. He begins by distinguishing the useful from the honorable. The emperor Tiberius said, “The Roman people were accustomed to take vengeance on their enemies by open means, arms in hand, not by fraud or surreptitiously.” But Tiberius was an “imposter.” Montaigne proceeds somewhat differently. He is no Roman, no man of war. He is a peace negotiator. He too claims to proceed unsurreptitously. “I have an open way that easily insinuates itself and gains credit on first acquaintance. Pure naturalness and truth”—he adds, a touch sententiously—”in whatever age, still find their time and their place.” Indeed they do, but not quite in the seeming sense of Montaigne, here.
Is Montaigne too an imposter? Perish the thought, he exclaims. Those who so suspect “make my subtlety too subtle.” “There is no rule” in any “school” that could do what Montaigne does in his negotiations with the armed prophets of the French civil war. One might even say that great philosophers have been “too enslaved to exhibit reverence for the laws.” One should not “call dishonorable and foul” certain “natural actions that are not only useful but necessary.” A prince should “attribute” the necessity for certain actions to God’s action, “a blow from the divine rod.” After all, “no private utility is worthy of our doing… violence to our conscience.” Yes, but: When it is a matter of “the public utility,” and “when it is very apparent and very important”—well, that is another matter. With Montaigne as for Machiavelli, utility quietly replaces honor as the quintessential public virtue.
Certain actions, even if supremely useful, might impel a conscientious man to repentance. But as Montaigne looks at himself in old age he can only sigh, resignedly, “Now it is done.” And besides, he says immediately, he is being remade from one minute to the next. Somehow he is both irremediable and perpetually malleable, undeserving of legal chastisement and unable to conform to any rule. As an author he plays no role—grammarian, poet, jurist. He is himself, he is every man. That is, he plays all the roles. He basks in no glory. His immortality is in his universality, not his distinction. “I do not teach”—the people will not call to him, ‘Rabbi, Rabbi’—but he is a prophet without honor in his own country. Unlike the most honored prophet, he will not find honor or reverent obedience in some other country. Seeking honor can get you crucified; reverent obedience is unproductive. Montaigne is rather a sort of Socrates, leading the life of man “in conformity with its natural condition.” With Montaigne, nature replaces God as the source of ‘prophecy.’
To reach higher is to fail. “Those who in my time have tried to correct the world’s morals by new ideas, reform the superficial vices; the essential ones”—those useful and necessary?—”they leave as them they were, if they do not increase them; and increase is to be feared.” Montaigne says “Pythagoreans” but means Christians in criticizing those who “believe that they feel great regret and remorse within; but of amendment or correction, or interruption, they show us no sign.” There can be no radical conversion, no ‘new man.’ “Repentance does not properly apply to the things that are not in our power.” What Nietzsche says thunderously Montaigne says quietly: Love our own piece of fatum, will the eternal return. “If I had to live over again, I would live as I have lived.” that is a spear in the side of Christian renewal.
As for the philosophical life, like Jesus Socrates arranged his own death, but not out of martyrdom, not to save or transform human beings. Socrates arranged his own death because nature was turning out the lights. A philosopher will adapt to the circumstance, whether it be advancing age or the currently regnant folly that is public opinion. He will know that “the fairest souls are those that have the most variety and adaptability,” and that “life is uneven, irregular, and multiform movement.” The Montaignian Socrates does not point ‘up’ to unchanging forms but ‘around’ to changing ones. That goes for himself, too. “I would rather fashion my mind than furnish it.” Invoking God and Socrates, Montaigne praises useful knowledge.
Of the three kinds of association—with men, with women, with books—women are pleasant if beautiful and well-bred; men are pleasant and useful if they are of that “rarest type among us” who know how to converse. But books are neither so susceptible to aging as women nor so rare as the rarest men. Montaigne retires to his library, where he can read and pace. (This is no nihilistic Flaubert who thinks sitting down, to be caught by some sharp-eyed wanderer of the future.) But finally in his most private moments Montaigne is alone, unmoveable, enthroned. The admirer of Contr’un is secretly solitary, a monarch, a man alone, like Machiavelli’s prince, and even more like Machiavelli himself—in retirement, teaching the princes (he who denies he teaches), an unmoved mover in a skin that always changes its colors to math its background. Christianity presents the miracle of God in a human body. Montaigne presents the greater miracle of a god in the shape of the most inconspicuous reptile, not even so worrisome as a serpent.
How can such a weak, lowly chameleon achieve immortality, even rule generations to come more effectively than Jesus? Because Jesus’ followers have a secret weakness. They avert their eyes from death and look to Heaven. They seek vengeance upon atheists who do not aver their eyes; they fix their eyes vengefully upon atheists and other criminals, killing them because to the pious death is a frightening evil. They can be diverted by “the beauty of a contrary picture,” a picture of clemency and kindness winning honor, favor and good will. Political men can always be so diverted. as for the people, they can be diverted by some silly spectacle. Just be sure not to fall in love with your own diversion, as women sometimes do.
The free spirits can look at death without averting their eyes. For them there is la gaya scienza. La gaya scienza teaches that mind and body are really one. La gaya scienza will prefer health as the real good of human being. La gaya scienza will pursue a discreet policy of sexual liberation., recognizing that love and marriage are a dysfunctional couple. Montaigne here attacks fidelity, perhaps fidelity tout court. The key to many a Montaignian essay is to convert the images to their theological equivalents and then prepare to think unfaithful thoughts. Fidelity is itself a policy of diversion—specifically, of sublimation. But sublimation only rechannels natural passions, making them more powerful, converting them into fanaticism, violence. Montaigne diverts the diverted and perverts the perverted. La gaya scienza is never solemn, because men are such fools. “Our delights and our excrements have been lodged together pell-mell, and… the supreme sensual pleasure is attended, like pain, with faintness and moaning.” What god created such animals? And young M. Foucault, I see what you see, feel what you feel, but are you not altogether too serious, too much in earnest, about all these passions, exquisite limit-pleasures, and bondages? Are you sufficiently gay, mon ami?
When it comes to God, the judge of men’s follies, Montaigne mounts not the divine chariot but a down-to-earth coach. When tutoring a prince, “it is all too easy to impress liberality on a man who has the means to practice it all he wants at the expense of others.” Liberality in a prince goes as well with tyranny as with royalty. The real royal virtue is justice. Montaigne always tempers his justice not with mercy but with toleration. Central to Book III is chapter seven, “Of the disadvantage of greatness.” The advantage to being a king is that, like a preacher, you address the people, “an inexact judge, easy to dupe, easy to satisfy.” The disadvantage of kingly greatness is that you never really know yourself, know the truth—never can measure exactly your real abilities against those of others. Your real identity is consumed by your royalty. As solitary as a king but, unlike one, obscure, Montaigne knows himself and thereby has the advantage over kings, human and divine. His spirit someday will permeate the world.
Not that anyone should imitate him. He publishes his imperfections out of caritas, so that others can avoid them. But it is Montaigne’s courage and intelligence in debate that emerge here, not his weakness. Debating “in a small group and for my own sake,” he indulges in “a friendship that delights in the sharpness and rigor of its intercourse, as does love in bites and scratches that draw blood.” This is the advantage of ‘polytheism.’ On the Montaignian throne, there can still be dialogue, if not with rare friends then with good books, if not with good books than with one of the monarch’s many selves. This is Montaigne’s solution to the Machiavellian problem: How can the lone prince know? (Machiavelli’s, too? As when he retired to his chamber to dine on his true food?)
Turning from theological to philosophic dealings, then, “I am no philosopher.” No philosopher-king, at any rate, seeking to revolutionize the polis. Stay out of it. Leave it alone. Revolution only brings some worse tyranny. I am universal, no political philosopher at all—a cosmopolitan, a world unto myself. I do not cling to my own, including my own life. (Mirabile dictu, I am a survivor, though, am I not? Just lucky, I guess.) Facing death as I am, allow me to offer you my confession. You may notice that I change themes abruptly, use false essay titles, and so forth. But really “my ideas follow one another, but sometimes it is from a distance, and look at each other, but with a sidelong glance.” The “more casual and accidental” my remarks “seem,” the more beautiful they are. “It is my inattentive reader who loses my subject, not I.” I confess, but you are the one to do penance. Go back and read my essays again—the most exquisitely pleasurable penance one could endure.
You really must learn to husband your will. “I keep myself to myself.” As a result—to my astonishment—I am a political philosopher: “I have been able to take part in public affairs without departing a nail’s breadth from myself, and to give myself to others without taking myself from myself.” Now there is the true divine liberality. This divinity is entirely natural. “The laws of Nature teach us what we rightly need”; those who know them “distinguish subtly between the desires that come from her and those that come from the disorder of my imagination.” To be politic, don’t be partisan. My administration “passed without a mark or a trace.” My “gliding, obscure, and quiet life” rules people without their knowing it.
How can Montaigne do that? First he philosophizes without claiming knowledge of causes, at least of ultimate causes. What is a miracle? How would you know one if you saw one? Nature is as obscure as God. You can work wonders, quietly and over time, if you win people’s trust rather than insisting on their fidelity, if you confess your ignorance rather than your sins, if you do not try to explain too much. Be the Montaignian Socrates, not soaring to the good but pulling everything down to earth, “his own original and natural level.” Unlike Jesus, Socrates can be known: “He did a great favor to human nature by showing how much it can do for itself,” not, like Jesus, how much God has done for human nature. “I do not think it becomes us well to let ourselves be taught by a pagan”—Plato—”how great an impiety it is to expect no help from God that is simply his own and without our cooperation.” Or, as Algernon Sidney puts it, God helps those who help themselves. Good men have “nothing to fear from the gods,” Montaigne’s Socrates says. “We naturalists” know: To survive and to triumph, put on an open and useful-looking face. That way, everyone will want you to live, perhaps forever, and everyone will take your advice. Benjamin Franklin will read this, considering it carefully.
“We naturalists” know how to deal with the feverish disease of religious fanaticism. Let nature take its course. Gradually, the fire will burn out. Meanwhile, the prudent man will live, judging naturally, physically, by his own sensations, not by passionate beliefs or overwrought reasonings. (Machiavelli is even more precise: Do not hear, do not look, but touch.) “The most beautiful lives, to my mind, are those that conform to the common human pattern, with order, but without miracle and without eccentricity.” Without Jesus or (the Platonic) Socrates.
Montaigne points back to Machiavelli, ahead to Nietzsche. Like them, he opposes the imaginary republics, religious or philosophic. Like those philosophers, he is alone (except for them, one dead, the other far in the future, and a few others). But he proceeds differently. Unlike Machiavelli, Montaigne finds Christians not weakly self-divided but fanatical, leonine—even if they are at the core cowardly lions. He therefore uses the fox much more than the lion, staying in his den; when he ventures out, he pretends he’s just a lazy dog. Unlike Nietzsche, he doesn’t find Christianity in a state of decadence, ready to collapse after a few strong kicks. This Anti-Christ stays at home, never marching toward Jerusalem. The time is not right.
But the times may be ripening. Religion can be diverted, philosophy seized, with an image of a new, multiform, various, ever-changing sort of beauty. Descartes, Bacon, Locke, Montesquieu: Where would these gods of the new Olympus be, without Montaigne’s example? Montaigne’s conclusion is practically a beginning.
Recent Comments