Lecture delivered at the Lifelong Learning Seminar, Hillsdale College, Hillsdale, Michigan
On July 4, 2014, the New York Times published a new Declaration of Independence. You may have missed it. Written by Jennifer Barnett, who is described as “Teacher Leader in Residence for the Center for Teaching Quality” in North Carolina, the “Declaration for Teachers” mimics some of Thomas Jefferson’s language—although unlike Jefferson’s declaration which is a logical syllogism, this one consists merely of a series of assertions. “We hold these truths to be self-evident,” she bravely begins, “that all teachers are valuable, and that they are endowed by their skill and expertise with a certain inalienable right to lead.” What is more, “Educational systems must be designed to serve students, deriving their power from the consent of teachers. Whenever any school or system forgets its way, it is the right of the teachers to alter or abolish it.” Now, you may have assumed that local citizens governed public schools, and that consent for the establishment and maintenance of your schools came from such practices as school board elections and budget referendums. Well, silly you. “No longer will teachers allow what seems to be in direct object”—I think she means “opposition,” but vocabulary may not be her strongest suit—”to their service dictate what is best for students or their profession.” What we need, rather, are “teacher-powered schools” in which “teacher leadership” is, because it “ought to be,” “the foundation upon which education lies.”
The Center for Teaching Quality receives part of its funding from—you guessed it—the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation. So we know where their money comes from. But you may be asking, ‘Where do such astonishing notions as these come from?’ The answer in this case, and in almost all cases in American public education for the past hundred years, is the Gospel According to John—John Dewey, that is. My religious language is apt because in 1897 Dewey availed of such language himself, titling one of his most influential essays, “My Pedagogic Creed.” There he wrote, “The teacher is engaged, not simply in the training of individuals, but in the formation of the proper social life. I believe that every teacher should realize the dignity of his calling; that he is a social servant set apart for the maintenance of proper social order and the securing of right social growth. I believe that in this way the teacher always is the prophet of the true God and the usherer in of the true kingdom of God.” A teacher-leader, indeed, because “education is the fundamental method of social progress and reform,” “the only sure method of social reconstruction.” The true kingdom of God means just such a reconstructed human society, which means that the true God, according to the apostle of “My Pedagogic Creed,” is none other than humanity—as one would expect from one of the co-signers of the original 1933 version of “The Humanist Manifesto.” Previously, the word “humanism” had meant the practice of “the humanities”; a “humanist” was who practiced and taught languages, literature, philosophy, and the other “liberal arts.” The liberal arts composed the heart of the curriculum of the old universities, founded under the aegis of, first, the Catholic Church and then the Protestant churches. But the new humanism rejected the religious framework of the old liberal arts and took upon itself the model of social science, itself modeled on the applied mathematics of engineering and also upon the scientific method of experimentation–in this case, social experimentation.
If Ms. Barnett received her ideas indirectly from John Dewey, where did Dewey get them? Born in Vermont in 1859 (he probably didn’t get them there), Dewey received his Ph. D. at the Johns Hopkins University—as did the other of the two most important first-generation American progressives, Woodrow Wilson. Johns Hopkins was the first American university animated by the principles of German philosophy and modeled upon the German institution of the research university. German philosophy in America derived from the thought of the nineteenth-century philosopher, G. W. F. Hegel. Hegel put moral and political philosophy on an entirely new foundation, a foundation fundamentally opposed to the philosophic foundation of the American founding.
As you know, the American founders looked to the laws of nature and of nature’s God as the basis of moral and political right. All men are created equal, not in intelligence, character, or physical appearance but in their right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Those unalienable rights—as distinguished from the supposedly unalienable right of teacher-leaders to run our schools—are what governments are intended to secure. The U. S. Constitution constitutes the American federal government and serves as the supreme law of our land, under the laws of nature and of nature’s God.
Hegel disagreed. He regarded both natural right and the God of the Bible as myths. These myths had served humanity ‘back in their day’—Hegel regarded the teachings of the Bible as superior to the paganisms that they replaced—but ‘that was then and this is now.’ Humanity has outgrown such things.
What is real, not mythological, is history—history defined as the evolution of all matter and all energy toward their apex, toward their purpose—namely, the thoroughgoing domination of the human mind over all of nature. Politically and economically, this will mean a worldwide human society or world state. The role of education and of educators in this scheme is to serve each national state by leading each nation toward this new version of the kingdom of God. Thus the new, scientistic ‘humanism’ will serve a new liberalism—a liberalism defined not in terms of individual liberty or popular self-government but in terms of the liberation of all humanity from the shackles of nature and of the old religions in a fully rational world-state governed by bureaucracies staffed by university-educated experts in scientific administration.
Matter and energy taken together are manifestations of what Hegel calls the “Absolute Spirit.” The Absolute Spirit isn’t ‘holy’ or separate from ‘Creation.’ Rather, what the Bible calls ‘Creation’ or what the philosophers called ‘nature’ is a physical manifestation of the Absolute Spirit, which unfolds dialectically over time. These words that I am speaking, these thoughts that I am expressing, the brain, throat, vocal cords etc. with which I am expressing them, this podium, this room, and all of you are all instances of the Absolute Spirit in its unfolding. The dialectical character of the Absolute Spirit refers to the way in which it expands or grows not smoothly but by generating opposing or contradictory forces (intellectual, moral, physical) which clash and then join together in combination or ‘synthesis.’
In moral and intellectual life, conflict or contradiction causes individuals and groups to become ‘conscious’ of their opponents and their ideas. In his paradigmatic example of this, Hegel describes the ‘master-slave dialectic.’ Briefly, the cause whereby the Absolute Spirit has differentiated itself into the opposite persons of a master and his slave is that two free men fought, and the loser surrendered his freedom in exchange for a life in bondage, supposing it better to be a live dog than a dead lion. The slave will only recover his freedom if he deliberately risks his life to win his freedom—in Hegel’s vocabulary, to compel the master to ‘recognize’ him as a fellow human being. When that happens, a new epoch in both men’s personal ‘history’ will begin; when that kind of thing happens in a society, a new epoch of national and potentially of world ‘history’ will begin. The laws of ‘History’—now defined as the dialectical unfolding of the Absolute Spirit—replace the laws of nature and of nature’s God, which are now seen as inadequate conceptions of the Absolute Spirit. Under this new dispensation, sometimes called ‘historicism,’ human nature is reconceived as evolving, perfecting itself, moving toward the telos, the ‘end’ of history.
In America, Hegel’s ideas became prominent in the middle of the nineteenth century, seen in the school of thought known as the Saint Louis Hegelians. Hegel himself was scarcely a democrat, but in America, as Tocqueville would have predicted, Hegel’s theory became democratized, put into the service of social egalitarianism. German idealism had entered the United States by the 1830s with Ralph Waldo Emerson and his circle, the New England Transcendentalists. The Transcendentalists showed a serious interest in education and in politics, forming an important part of the Abolitionist movement, but they inclined toward individualism and resisted statism. But in 1856 an eccentric Prussian thinker named Henry Conrad Brokmeyer settled in St. Louis after working first as a mechanic, then a businessman in the years after arriving in the United States at the age of 16. Two years later, he befriended William Torrey Harris, a transplant from New England. Brokmeyer and Harris studied Hegel’s Logic together, founding a philosophic circle propounding, among other notions, that the leading edge of world history was moving from Europe to the United States and establishing its intellectual capital in—where else?—St. Louis, soon to become (as they imagined) the new Athens. The Civil War provided them with what they regarded as proof positive of Hegelianism: a massive dialectical clash, would lead to the introduction of a genuine modern state in the postwar historical ‘synthesis’ of North and South. Brokmeyer went on to a serious political career in Missouri, rising as high as acting Governor of Missouri before failing to win the governorship in the next election and eventually retreating to life in Indian territory farther to the west (did I mention he was eccentric?). Harris enjoyed greater success and a less checkered career, which included service as head of the U. S. Education Commission beginning in the late 1880s.
Several years after the war they founded the Hegelian Journal of Speculative Philosophy, which published translation of Hegelian and other German philosophic texts along with articles by a number of young American philosophers, including John Dewey. Dewey had come to Hegelianism in the 1880s at the Johns Hopkins University, where his mentor was another Saint Louis Hegelian, George Sylvester Morris. Another graduate student at Hopkins at the time was Woodrow Wilson. Both Dewey and Wilson went on to eminent careers in education: Wilson, with a Ph. D. in the newly-invented field of political science, eventually becoming president of Princeton, and Dewey initially at the University of Michigan as a philosophy professor (Morris arranged for his appointment), then at the University of Chicago (another German-style research university), but then and most strategically at Columbia University, and particularly at its famous Teacher’s College—for decades the most prestigious college for professional educators in the United States.
For Dewey, Wilson, and for the American Progressives generally, the American founding—based upon the old philosophy of liberty, the old liberalism of natural right—was good for its time, but now obsolete. A new liberalism was needed, one based upon historical right or progress and not the unalienable, natural rights of the old Declaration of Independence that the old Constitution was designed to secure. The new, “elastic,’ “organic,” or “living” Constitutional would systematically ‘grow’ the central state, providing employment for university-trained, tenured administrators and public school teachers. Thus the liberal education that formed the minds of the American founders was also obsolete, and must be replaced by a new liberal education for the new liberalism or administrative statism. In the first years of the twentieth century, the professional classes would form the core of the Progressive movement in its major political campaigns, often in alliance with the older but now fading Populist movement. The number of ‘professionals’ surged in those decades, as the shift from a commercial-agricultural to a commercial-industrial economy spawned large national corporations and a population shift into the cities. Both the new corporations and the big cities needed professional administrators, making the Hegelian fondness for bureaucracy much more plausible than it had been in the previous centuries here.
According to the democratized Hegelians of the Progressive movement, philosophy, which had once attempted to understand human nature as something fixed and imperfect, must now dedicate itself to social, economic, and political progress aimed at perfecting human societies. Dewey shares with Marx—another disciple of Hegel—a rejection of natural right and an esteem for social egalitarianism. He came to share with Marx an evolutionary form of materialism, moving some distance from Hegel on this point. But he sharply disagrees with Marx, and thus opposed Soviet Communism, on two crucial matters: the regime of the dictatorship of the proletariat and the use of class warfare (an economic form of the ‘dialectic’) as the means of human progress. Rather, according to the Gospel of John Dewey, education via the scientific method is the true vehicle of social change; education should serve not a ‘top-down’ regime of dictatorship but a democratic regime of social experimentation and pluralism.
With Dewey the school is now reconceived as the laboratory of social progress. Children must not compete against one another in school. They should learn by cooperating with one another in group projects. “I believe that all education proceeds by the participation of the individual in the social consciousness of the [human] race,” Dewey wrote in. “My Pedagogic Creed.” “The most formal and technical education in the world cannot safely depart from this general process. It can only organize it; or differentiate it in some particular direction.” Education rightly understood is the handmaiden of ‘history.’
Such participation—along with such direction—begins not with intellectual training but with what we now call ‘hands-on’ projects: cooking, sewing, manual training of various sorts. This program (consistent with Brokmeyer’s example as a philosopher-craftsman) was intended to fuse the mentality of the working class with the mentality of the intellectual class, all in the service of forming one all-encompassing class of citizens who were socially equal, not equal merely in terms of natural rights. The state, as Dewey conceived of it, following Hegel, is an organic unity, an organism, which harmonizes the relations of all social associations within it, including the careful regulation of business. The school is the brain of the social organism that is the state. The teacher thus does indeed become the true leader of human society, along with other professional public administrators who form part of the modern state’s nervous system, the bureaucracy.
To give you an idea of how far Dewey sought to ‘socialize’ human life, going far beyond mere socialism in economics or democracy in politics, I only mention his theory of how children learn. All children are essentially ‘groupish’ organisms. “The only true education comes through the stimulation of the child’s powers by the demands of the social situations in which he finds himself.” When Dewey says that “all education proceeds by the participation of the individual in the social consciousness of the race,” he gives the example of the human infant. It is (he claims) “through the response which is made to the child’s instinctive babblings [that] the child comes to know what the babblings mean.” Now, my own impression is that children already know exactly what their instinctive babblings mean. It is rather for the parents to figure out what the child is babbling about, and then to decide whether the child should get what he wants. It is further for the child then to understand the language in which the parents command, cajole, and teach him. After understanding that language, including the word that forms sentences like, “No! and, after some schooling, “All men are created equal,” the child can then move on to live a meaningful life in the service of the God who created the terms and conditions of life, including the nature governed by His laws. That is the kind of primary education which culminated in the old liberal education seen in the colleges and universities of Europe and America, the education which formed the old liberalism—the liberalism of self-government, of individual and citizen liberty.
But Dewey has other plans.
The key to understanding Dewey’s philosophy is an appreciation of his concept of “growth.” “Growth” combines the organicism of Darwinian biology with the progressivism of contemporary social science. Teachers should never “impose certain ideas” or “form certain habits” in the child. “The only way of securing continuity in the child’s growth” is for the school to “represent life”—initially, the child’s life at home, with its cooking and cleaning and carpentry, but mostly through the teachers who will arrange the social environment of the school and then nudge the child to respond (as Dewey says) “properly” to that environment. And what is “properly”? Nothing other than “a continuing reconstruction of experience…. The process and the goal of education are one and the same thing.” “What we term reason is primarily the law of orderly or effectual action.” Thus “I believe that education is the fundamental method of social progress and reform,” because “education is the regulation of the process of coming to share in the social consciousness”; “the art of… giving shape to human powers and adapting then to social service is the supreme art.” If so, then of course the teacher is the supreme artist and the teacher of teachers—Professor Dewey himself—the most supreme of all. But even he is only the agent of History, which is nothing other than “the life and progress of humanity.” If the Absolute Spirit replaces the Holy Spirit, then History replaces Providence. The meaning of “properly” rests on Dewey’s claim that “ultimate moral motives and forces are nothing more or less than social intelligence—the power of observing and comprehending social situations—and social power—trained capacities of social control—at work in the service of social interests and aims.”
Speaking of human sociality, I hope that I am not alone in seeing a certain circularity in Dewey’s moral reasoning. This comes from partial departure from Hegelian historicism, which he takes in an egalitarian direction. In Hegel, the dialectical unfolding of the Absolute Spirit has come to an end in his own systematic account of all aspects of human life. There will be no more fundamentally new ideas. In practice, as I’ve noted, the Absolute Spirit will continue to progress towards the World State, a political condition which Hegel’s thought has already prepared. But Dewey denies that there is an ‘end of History,’ but only endless process and alleged progress toward more extensive democracy. He wrote, famously, “The cure for the ills of democracy is… more democracy.” Similarly, the purpose of utility is more utility, as seen in Dewey’s remark that “it is the characteristic use to which a thing is put… which supplies the meaning with which it is identified,” and the meaning shifts with the use). The purpose of education is more education. The purpose of more growth is more growth. And so on. Or, as Dewey quite openly argues, human life is not “a preparatory probation for ‘another life,'” on earth or in Heaven, nor is it a struggle to fulfill the potential of human nature: indeed, “the conception that growth and progress are just approximations to a final unchanging goal is the last infirmity of the mind in its transition from a static to a dynamic understanding of life.” Take that, Hegel. Endless construction and reconstruction is our lot and indeed, as far as Dewey is concerned, our joy.
Dewey teaches that “to an extent characteristic of no other institution, save that of the state itself, the school has the power to modify the social order.” But of course “the selection and prosecution of the detailed ways and means by which the public will is to be executed efficiently must remain largely a matter of specialized and expert service.” Parents and other citizens generally may have a say in determining the ends of education and of judging the results, but otherwise the expert professionals will rule. “Genuine social control means the formation of a certain mental disposition; a way of understanding, objects, events, and acts which enables one to participate effectively in associated activities.” The experts will serve as the facilitator/controllers of children and therefore of society and therefore of the course of history. But why is this not merely purposefulness without a purpose?
All of this leads to an obvious political problem: If the daily rule of experts (albeit in the name of democracy) puts itself at the service of somewhat vague and circular purposes—if what Dewey and his allies called “pragmatism” results in a process of endless social experimentation—then why will this not eventuate in a power-politics of nihilism. This new power-politics would be fought out not so much in parliaments or even on battlefields as in classrooms and school administrators’ offices. Does this not expose the real purpose of historicism-without-an-end-of-History as the exercise of the will to power? The great philosopher of the will to power isn’t the constitutional monarchist, Hegel, or the democrat, Dewey, but Nietzsche.
Filter Hegel through the habits of mind and heart of a democratic society and you get Dewey and Wilson. Filter Nietzsche through the habits of mind and heart of a democratic society and you get the various advocates of ‘postmodernism.’ With postmodernism, modern education, beginning in the universities, re-divided what Dewey and his allies had attempted to unite: vocational and pre-professional training on the one hand—which has become the focus of so many former liberal-arts colleges—and a reconceived liberal arts curriculum dedicated to ‘deconstructing’ the thoughts and careers of your enemies, privileging ‘in’ groups over ‘out’ groups, playing ‘gotcha’ with words, and generally re-inventing illiberal education in the guise of egalitarianism.
All of this operates at far remove from liberty and equality as understood by the Founders—as inherent or natural rights, secured better or worse by political institutions but unaltered by them and given by our Creator and not by governments. It is to that form of equality and liberty that Hillsdale College continues to be dedicated.
Further reading:
Dewey was a long-lived and prolific philosopher. In addition to “My Pedagogic Creed” see also Democracy and Education (originally published in 1944), The Public and Its Problems (originally published in 1927), and Individualism Old and New (originally published in 1929). All are still in print. For an excellent summary of Dewey’s political philosophy, see Robert H. Horwitz: “Dewey,” in Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds.: The History of Political Philosophy (originally published in 1963, with several subsequent editions).
G. W. F. Hegel: Elements of the Philosophy of Right. H. B. Nisbet trans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. See also Steven B. Smith: Hegel’s Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1989).
Recent Comments